Discuss-2
| |
Philosophy vs.
Literature
|
|
Brad Pitt as Achilles
in Troy |
Detail of "The
School of Athens" by Raphael Plato and Aristotle |
Overview:
As
human beings mature into greater awareness, a question arises that is the central inquiry
of philosophy: How shall I live? This has been translated and elaborated in
numerous directions, through many disciplines, so that it is often restated as: What is the meaning of life? Who am I? What
is truth? With a thousand worlds for the
asking, how best to spend the time given to me?
If
early wisdom is any guide, we might lend an ear to Aristotle, who simply says, the person
who knows most is likely to live best. For
Aristotle, the highest state of human perfection is in the contemplation of truth. Whether a truth can be determined through
sustained analytical thinking, or, if it must be held up against the authentic,
spontaneous response of deeply felt emotions, this is the point of much friction between
philosophy and the arts. The source of this
disagreement may be traced to the ancient debate between Plato and Aristotle. That Plato felt hostile towards the emotions
aroused by literature and the arts, and denounced them as a means of learning, has been
the cause of much distress for its practitioners, supporters and teachers.
I
would like to take the time here to examine how this disagreement came about, especially
how it has played a role in promoting a negative attitude towards the arts that has
persisted up to today. Nussbaum (14) tells us
that before Plato, Greek tragedians recognized the ethical significance of learning
through emotional experience. In other words,
the ancient Greeks did not divide the poetic from the philosophical. What brought about such a change? In the next section I will attempt to clarify the
issues surrounding this argument in order to set forth certain concepts that I will
revisit in later sections.
The
Paradox of Plato
Both
Plato (428-347 B.C.) and the poets agreed their aim
was to investigate human life and how to live it, but where they and later Aristotle
(384-322 B.C.) parted company was over the nature of
understanding and ethical truth. For
modern readers to comprehend Platos stance, we must slant our thinking towards the
culture in Greece at that time.
The
pre-Socratics were basically oral thinkers, strongly rooted in the traditions of the past. Of Xenophanes,
Heraclitus and Parmenides, the three whose work has survived, what we notice first is a
strange way of speaking, not merely due to certain verbal and metrical habits but in their
expression or mental attitude. (Havelock x). This
is because they were embedded in myth, these thinker-poets, and their means of expression
was through recitation. By this period
various tribes of people had invented their own religions and mythologies that were
related to the Greeks but with slight differences. Further
abroad, there were even more different systems of explaining the world in terms of
spiritual values and dogma. In the first
millennium B.C. these systems began to converge on
Greece, situated as it was at the crossroads of Africa, Persia, the Middle East, Europe
and the surrounding city-states of the Mediterranean.
Wherever cultures with strong ideas rub up against each other, there follows
a competition for the hearts and minds of the people.
Because the nature of religion and deity-based mythologies is such that no
one group could accept anothers beliefs, Helladic Greece became a crucible for
religious and mythological strife. (Hughes/Abbs 162).
The
struggle to find a peaceful equilibrium was equally strong and the early philosophers
became the heroes of the conflict. It
created them, opened up depths of spiritual imagination as they attempted to impose order
and make sense of it all. Religious passion
was transformed in the philosopher to an awareness of the sacredness and seriousness of
life. Obscure symbolic mysteries in the
mythologies became for the philosophers a perception of universal, human truths. A tectonic shift was underway. What followed was the apogee of ancient Greece,
the great fifth century B.C., which saw the waning
of the religious era and the waxing of the philosophical. (163).
Yet
during Platos lifetime, in the early days of Greek rationalism, religious symbolism
and ritual still exerted great influence. (Havelock ix).
Perhaps more importantly, Plato viewed this era in Greek civilization as one
of quasi-morality. As part of their training,
the young were taught that although virtue was important, it was often difficult and
unrewarding. In the Republic, Plato
has written a guide book where he attempts to isolate the principle of morality in the
abstract, to be defined and defended for its own sake, and to set forth what he believed
would be the happiest human condition. Never
before had pure morality been envisioned as a goal for society and its individuals. The Republic, ultimately then, came
to be written as an indictment of Greek tradition and its educational system, as well as
an attempt to create order from the cultural chaos of the time. (12). |
Today we find it
strange that the title of Platos work is not wholly indicative of the contents. In fact, Book III and X are occupied with an
examination of the arts, not politics. In
these Books and in many of his other works, Plato focuses blame for Greeces state of
gray morality upon the poets. (3). In a
remarkable statement in the Republic (398A) he says that if a dramatic poet tried
to visit the ideal state he would be escorted to the border. In other works such as the Laws he takes a
stronger line, recommending stringent censorship of the poets. (Murdoch Existentialists
and Mystics [unless otherwise noted] 386).
This attitude has puzzled thinkers for centuries. Was not Plato himself a poet in his youth? Did he not frequent dramatic performances? And what about the Republic is it
not arranged artistically in the form of dialogues with a beauty of range, universality,
depth of human emotion, economy and commanding power?
If we are to understand his meaning we must take a harder look at his
conception of philosophy.
Plato describes existence as a life-long
pilgrimage from appearance to reality. Awareness
moves from blanket acceptance of sense experience to a more complex and morally
enlightened understanding. This is laid out
in Platos Theory of Forms, derived from Socratess search for moral definitions
and the beliefs of Heraclitus. The Theory of
Forms wrestles with the questions that most concerned Plato: Why do so many different things share similar
qualities? How do we know things in a world
that is in continual flux? And, what is
virtue and how can we learn it and know it? The
Forms are put forth as changeless, eternal, non-sensible objects that can provide some
answers. As guarantors of the unity and
objectivity of morals and therefore the reliability of knowledge, the Forms remain steady
and true. (Murdoch 387). In the Republic
(596A) Plato tells us that there are Forms for groups of things, such as mathematical
Forms and logical Forms, even sensa Forms such as Beauty. The Form of the Good appears as an awakening and
creative force. (Murdoch 387).
Interestingly, Plato tells us that we are
innately aware of the Forms because before we were born we possessed all knowledge. This is an argument in favor of the immortality of
the soul. Life then is composed of stages of anamnesis,
the recovery of forgotten knowledge, which can be accessed through training or guidance. (388).
Plato elucidates this concept through his myth
of the sun, the fire and the cave (Republic 514). The pilgrimage through life begins with prisoners
in a cave. In the lowest levels of existence
the prisoners are only able to see shadows on a wall cast by the fire. Later they move into a new level of reality and
are able to see the fire, which makes the shadows. After
they escape the cave they realize that the outside world is illuminated by the sun, and
ultimately, in the highest level, they can apprehend the sun itself. The sun stands for the Form of the Good by which
humans are able to see the truth. (Murdoch 389).
|
How does this relate to art? Plato describes the distance of art from the Forms
through the example of a painting of a bed. The
Form of a bed is eternal; it is a pure essence, an ideal.
When a carpenter builds a bed, it is one step removed from the ideal Form. But an artist who copies this bed from her point
of view is therefore at a third remove from reality.
She doesnt understand the Form of the bed, nor has she made a functioning
physical piece of furniture. And moreover,
since she avoids confronting the disparity between the appearance of the bed and the Form,
her art willfully accepts appearance without questioning it.
Thus Plato accuses the poets of being undignified or immoral. (390). Their work is at best frivolous and at worst
dangerous, to science and morality. For this
reason, Plato recommends the major Greek poets from Homer to Euripides be excluded from
the Greek educational system. (Havelock 3-4).
For modern thinkers there has been great reluctance to take what Plato
says at face value. One of the main
arguments, Havelock (6) states, is that the experience of poetry today has an
aesthetic dimension that was lacking in Platos day. That is, we now accept that the experience of
poetry can offer a particular kind of aesthetic understanding, one that appeals to us
through the senses, feelings and intuition. But
Plato reacts to the elements of poetry as though they are a type of psychic poison. He charges the poet with contriving to distort
meaning through the use of language (Republic 601A) or embellishing meaning by
exploiting the resources of meter, rhythm and harmony.
To us, this seems to be violating the heart of the poetic experience. Plato goes on to say,
In
the same way the poet can use words and phrases as a medium to paint a picture of any
craftsman, though he knows nothing except how to represent him, and the meter and rhythm
and music will persuade people who are as ignorant as he is, and who judge merely from his
words, that he really has something to say about shoemaking or generalship or whatever it
may be. So great is the natural magic of
poetry. Strip it of its poetic coloring,
reduce it to plain prose, and I think you know how little it amounts to. (601A)
All Platos efforts run contrary to our idea of poetry for
poetrys sake, especially as a means of communicating experience. And it is important at this stage to recall that
the Republic was partly written as a manual for educational reform. His objections are in the context of the standards
he was setting in terms of education. For him
then, poetry is a threat to education due to a moral danger as well as an intellectual
one. It clouds values, good character and
prevents perception of the truth. (Havelock 6).
Today in education we defend poetry as morally uplifting, inspiring us to
higher levels of consciousness, deeper compassion and making us more aesthetically adept
at reaching out to new and ineffable ways of describing those realities which escape
prosaic articulation. But this is a modern
prejudice and many thinkers have attempted to rescue Plato in order to make him more
palatable to modern tastes. Havelock (7)
counteracts such attempts by saying if the programme of the Republic is
utopian and that the exclusion of poetry applies only to an ideal condition not realizable
in the recognisable future or in earthly societies
(then) why should the Muse of all
people be selected for exclusion from Utopia?
this
depends
on the assumption that the Republic (so-called) is about politics. Is that not the label on the bottle? Yes, it is, but
in this instance (it) reports
a strong flavour of educational but not of political theory. The reforms which are proposed are considered to
be urgent in the present and are not utopian. Poetry
is not charged with a political offense but an intellectual one and accordingly the
constitution which has to be protected against her influence is twice defined as the
polity within the soul.
Another deflection of Platos assault is to refocus his target a
little left of poetry on to that of drama. In
his desire for a life of virtuous moderation, we may say that Plato was a puritan, and
like most puritans, Plato disliked theatre. Public
performance is at home with vulgarity, buffoonery, histrionic emotion and even scandal. Aristocratic taste is sometimes offended by gaudy
showmanship, rude sounds and behavior, displayed especially by the mob mentality of the
crowd. (Murdoch 397). The fear that words might provoke deeds led Plato
to urge his followers to be content with the more sedate writer who would reproduce the
speech of the decent man. (Republic 398B). Of
course Plato has a point in some respects about the cheapening and cruel effects of an
atmosphere where everything can be mocked and rendered ludicrous. (Murdoch 398). |
|
But I would reiterate here that Plato is
hugely concerned with the emotional impact on the audience.
In particular, he points a finger at the poets use of mimesis, or
imitation, which caused the audience, as well as the actors and the poet himself, to
identify emotionally with the characters in the play.
It is this pathology of fluctuating emotions, he says, with which we feel but never
think and the submission to the hypnotic effect of the poets skills that is the root
of the problem. The damage is caused by being
under the spell of an artists imperfect view of things and the audiences
identification with that view. (Havelock 26).
Now we begin to see that Platos argument is concerned with people
identifying with flawed role models, not just the noble heroes. In so being affected, people might be encouraged
to adopt lower behavior, much like our modern worries about viewers mimicking TV, film or
video game violence. It is the irrational
emotional power of art, along with its power to tell lies or subversive truths, that puts
us significantly at risk, according to Plato. (Murdoch 13).
There is nothing left for it but censorship. If we take the stories of gods,
heroes and human beings seriously, full as they are of murder, incest, treachery,
uncontrolled passions, weakness and cowardice, I feel we could agree with Plato that after
a time the repetition of this hazardous material may lead to copycat behavior by those
with undeveloped minds. |
Heraklion, Theatre at
Gortyn |
|
If it were only this, we might be able to
understand Platos objection. But he
leaves off criticizing the content of the stories to examine the manner in which they are
told. He begins to reveal a fundamental
hostility to the poetic experience per se, and especially to the imaginative act which
makes up such a large portion of that experience. (Havelock 10-11).
Why does Plato view poetry as such a menace to the moral fabric of his
society? We must recall that up to this time,
the poets were the only means of transmitting knowledge in a pre-literate society. Poetry circulated a massive repository of useful
information, in effect a veritable encyclopedia of ethics, politics, history, culture and
even skills, such as the proper way to load and unload ships. An indoctrination rather than an entertainment,
poetry was the core of the able citizens educational equipment. Once this is grasped, we can begin to understand
that the Republic is an attack on the existing, traditional system.
In the tenth book of the Republic Plato takes issue with the idea
that the poets ought to know about the techniques and subjects of which they speak. Homer, Plato contends, attempts to discuss
warfare, military leadership, politics and education, when in fact, Homer had very little
practical experience in most of these areas. Yet
Homer is so convincing in relating these subjects that he is admired for his expert
knowledge. Plato goes to great
lengths here to illustrate the enormous gulf between the truth as understood by reason and
the illusions produced by poetry. (28).
All of this strikes us as foreign to our modern way of thinking. We assume the poet is an artist who creates works
of art. But for Plato the concept of
aesthetics never enters the discussion. He
persists in criticizing the poets for not teaching well.
(29). I tend to agree with the literary critic, Harold Bloom (6), who sees
this as Platos deep and personal resentment towards the poets. Bloom claims that as Plato became more aware of
the hold poetry had over societys imagination, he began to recognize the
agon, or competition with philosophy. It
matters little if it is geographical, religious, or philosophical; the struggle for
ideological dominance is inevitable as education systems are put into place. (Eisenberg 36).
The lesson in Homer is the glory of battle, the strengths and weaknesses in
each of us, and so Homer teaches the poetics of conflict.
And all of Plato is an incessant conflict with Homer. Worse, all of Platos efforts were in vain,
Bloom (6) says, because it was the voice of Homer, not Plato, that was the continued
schoolbook of the ancient Greeks.
We might concede that this kind of attack is fair if Homer is actually
intending to provide a manual on the manufacture of beds, etc. If that is so, it is a poor manual. It is indeed not based on practical experience or
understanding. In contrast to art,
Platos Theory of Forms is epistemological and wishes to define the kinds of
knowledge that would be described as universal, precise and final. (Havelock 30).
Perhaps the most surprising revelation is that if poetrys primary
purpose was to provide a social encyclopedia, one that Plato defined through the standards
of his Academy as functioning badly, it was because the goal of his curriculum was
expressed by the word episteme, which is often translated into English as
science. A graduate of the
Academy possessed rigorous training in mathematics and logic, which Plato deemed most
necessary to a society he believed ought to be organized along scientific lines. (31). |
|
A Roman mosaic
showing Plato's Academy |
However, I would still like to question why
Plato chose such an easy scapegoat for all of societys woes. What role exactly did Plato see poetry as playing? The answer to this last part of the puzzle may lie
in Platos difficulty in discussing poetry as separate from the conditions under
which it is performed. This leads us to
believe the actual performance of poetry was much more crucial to Greek culture than we
might realize. These were not selected
readings held in public or private venues nor kept to festival days in the theatre. These performances were in fact a fundamental
part of adult recreation. People did not go
to the bookshop or library to pick up a copy of The Iliad and read it at home. The relationship between the audience and the
poet was always that of listeners at an oral performance. (Havelock 37-38).
The Greeks had been using the alphabet since the 8th century B.C. but as with any new technology it was slow to spread. Its appearance did not necessarily imply full
literacy. Reading must be introduced at the
primary level, not the secondary, and records show that as late as the 5th century B.C., Athenians were taught to read as adolescents. The skill was therefore overlaid upon previous
oral learning. We can assume then that along
with a dominant oral learning style, there also persisted an oral state of mind, and for
Plato, this was the main enemy, for the manner of thinking determines the connection of
the group. (40-41). The terms of thinking
become standardized so that the group recognizes a clear identity and shares a singular
consciousness with a similar set of values. And
to maintain a standardized identity a group must take action to preserve a certain body of
knowledge. In the form of language, for
example, information will be passed on to others about methods of building a house or
cooking food. Paradigms will be drilled into
successive generations. (42).
In a pre-literate society, this living knowledge is retained through
storytelling. But how can such detailed
instruction be transmitted from person to person over multiple generations without losing
its precision? The answer was, as Havelock
(42) puts it, to use a particular verbal technology based on rhythmic wording
that was constructed cleverly enough in metrical patterns so as to imprint sound, shape
and meaning on the listeners psyche. All memorization in this tradition required
continual repetitive recitation. The body of
knowledge was repeated at the banquet, family rituals, and in the public theatre and
marketplace. Parents, elders, students and
professionals participated in a community conspiracy to keep its precious knowledge alive.
(43-44).
How is such a body of memory to be acquired, not just by the professionals
but by the average members of the group? We
have alluded to it earlier as an appeal to psychic resources, sometimes latent but
available in the consciousness of each person. It
is actually accomplished by a collusion between poet and listener. The Homeric poet knew he controlled the culture in
which he lived and this was a fact accepted by the community and himself without
reflection or analysis. He was highly aware
of the skills he used to imprint ideas on memory but the actual methods he employed were
personal unto himself. It is this personal
power that alarms Plato. Both what the poet
was saying and how it was being said was being accepted without question because the
Homeric audience submitted gratefully to the pleasurable, hypnotic effect of the
poets art.
Let us spend a moment showing how this was done, in particular by Homer,
and by literature in general. Partly it is
accomplished by the marriage of words to dance rhythms. (145-146). If we look closely at this technique, we compare
the easiest way to memorize, and that is through sheer repetition,
Hector is dead; Hector is dead.
This, however, has little force. But
compare it to the increased energy of the following,
Hector is dead; dead indeed is Hector.
where the words and meaning are the same but now
we have a more unusual word order.
If the mind chooses to take a further creative step, keeping the same
essential image but taking a different angle on it or utilizing unexpected words or
syntax, it can be restated in a more appealing way,
Hector is dead; fallen is Hector
Yea Achilles slew him
Hector is defeated, Hector is dead.
Such is the virtuosity found in The Iliad. The minds eye is bifocal; it sees meaning
but it makes room for differences within the meaning.
In addition to this is the parallel system of repetition that concentrates
on sound alone, outside of meaning. In the
example of,
Hector is dead; Hector is dead.
the units of repetition are two-fold, the dactylic
hexameter in the Greek is proportioned between lines of constant time length. The result feels like slow regular undulations,
which in turn are composed of an internal pattern of ripples of wavelengths. In other words, the rhythmic memory constantly
repeats itself. (Havelock 147-148).
The voice falls naturally into these rhythms, and as if that were not
enough, other parallel rhythms reinforce it. A
reciter uses a lyre and his strumming sets up an acoustic rhythm in addition to the vocal
cords, which add to the pattern of bodily reflexes. Thus
the listeners ears are doubly affected by two sets of sounds in concordant rhythm,
voice and instrument. The latter, however, is
merely repetitive, otherwise it would detract from the main attention. Lastly, there is the body itself. The fingers, legs and feet are controlled in a
pattern of actions akin to dancing, which aid in acting out the recital. And this lulling, throbbing motion invites the
audience to enter the poets trance and shadow the motions of the reciter, perhaps
only half known to the listener herself, and soon the listener is accompanying the beat
with a rocking motion or a foot tap of her own that keeps with the bodys overall
rhythm. (148-150). |
This is how the poet moves the audience and
now we will go inside the listener herself to learn how a person is affected. The recital of the social and cultural
encyclopedia was an adult recreation but it could also be said that it was a great
pleasure. The audience was quite willing to
spend time under the poets spell so as to let go of their cares and relax. Poets were often praised for releasing their
listeners from anxiety and grief. (152-153).
The pleasure of letting go while at the same time coding the information
into the memory awakened another psychic phenomenon, that of fully identifying with the
actor or character in the performance. A
listener as well as a reciter had to access her own previously experienced grief or anger
in order to connect to that of Achilless. In
effect, the actor or listener became Achilles.
If this was achieved, a person could recall the story of Achilles for the
rest of her life, quoting the story, line for line. The
cost of this mental effort, of course, was a complete loss of objectivity. And here we are again at Platos complaint
about the arts.
I would emphasize the importance of his choice of the word mimesis
to describe the poetic experience which becomes more significant when we understand that
it does not only apply to the poet representing Forms at a third remove. The actor upon the stage is imitating a character
who represents a hero or god, and the members of the audience themselves are following the
words, sounds and body rhythms so closely that they are possibly mimicking the movements
of the reciter which in turn helps them enter the trance more fully. The vivid experience of the work enables them to
remember the story they are hearing. For
Plato, this kind of learning, this emotional reliving of experience through the memory
over and over again instead of learning through rational analysis, is for him the worst
aspect of it. For in the oral tradition,
there is such an immediate impact upon the listener that the emotions rush forth and there
can be no clear-headed understanding of the information that is being delivered, no
critical distance nor objectivity that would allow for determination of the truth. (Bailin, in conversation.). And again, for Plato, this is the chief obstacle
to the ideal method of learning as deemed by the Academy, that of scientific rationalism. (Havelock 45, 47).
In the end, Plato was to have his way.
As literacy spread in Europe, the oral tradition is all but lost to us. From classical Greece on to our day, rational
thinking and science appear to be winning over more and more hearts and minds. In our modern society, the arts continue to suffer
from Platos decree that they cannot be a form of knowledge. The great paradox of Plato is that his masterpiece
of thought is great art, yet it is something he never theoretically realized. (Murdoch 13).
I will continue to bring up Plato in later sections when his ideas relate
to issues I will discuss. Ancient Greece did
produce a great defender of literature, someone for whom emotion played a large role in
discovering truth. As we shall see in Week 3,
one of Platos students took up arts cause and argued in favor of its ability
to provide a way of learning. (excerpted
from: Barber, Susan. The Immediacy of Writing:
Why Literature Matters More to Students Who Are Creative Writers. SFU MA thesis. 2004) |
Philosophy
Background: Why do human beings behave justly? Is it because they fear
societal punishment? Are they trembling before notions of divine retribution? Do the
stronger elements of society scare the weak into submission in the name of law? Or do
humans behave justly because it is good for them to do so? Is justice, regardless of its
rewards and punishments, a good thing in and of itself? How do we define justice? Plato
sets out to answer these questions in the Republic.
He wants to define justice, and to define it in such a way as to show that justice is
worthwhile in and of itself. He meets these two challenges with a single solution: a
definition of justice that appeals to human psychology, rather than to perceived behavior.
|
|
Platos strategy in the Republic
is to first explicate the primary notion of societal, or political, justice, and then to
derive an analogous concept of individual justice. In Books II, III, and IV, Plato
identifies political justice as harmony in a structured political body. An ideal society
consists of three main classes of peopleproducers (craftsmen, farmers, artisans,
etc.), auxiliaries (warriors), and guardians (rulers); a society is just when relations
between these three classes are right. Each group must perform its appropriate function,
and only that function, and each must be in the right position of power in relation to the
others. Rulers must rule, auxiliaries must uphold rulers convictions, and producers
must limit themselves to exercising whatever skills nature granted them (farming,
blacksmithing, painting, etc.) Justice is a principle of specialization: a principle that
requires that each person fulfill the societal role to which nature fitted him and not
interfere in any other business. |
At the end of Book IV, Plato tries
to show that individual justice mirrors political justice. He claims that the soul of
every individual has a three part structure analagous to the three classes of a society.
There is a rational part of the soul, which seeks after truth and is responsible for our
philosophical inclinations; a spirited part of the soul, which desires honor and is
responsible for our feelings of anger and indignation; and an appetitive part of the soul,
which lusts after all sorts of things, but money most of all (since money must be used to
fulfill any other base desire). The just individual can be defined in analogy with the
just society; the three parts of his soul achieve the requisite relationships of power and
influence in regard to one another. In a just individual, the rational part of the soul
rules, the spirited part of the soul supports this rule, and the appetitive part of the
soul submits and follows wherever reason leads. Put more plainly: in a just individual,
the entire soul aims at fulfilling the desires of the rational part, much as in the just
society the entire community aims at fulfilling whatever the rulers will.
The parallels between the just society and the just
individual run deep. Each of the three classes of society, in fact, is dominated by one of
the three parts of the soul. Producers
are dominated by their appetitestheir urges for money, luxury, and pleasure.
Warriors are dominated by their spirits, which make them courageous. Rulers are dominated
by their rational faculties and strive for wisdom. Books V through VII focus on the rulers
as the philosopher kings.
In a series of three analogiesthe allegories of the
sun, the line, and the cavePlato explains who these individuals are while hammering
out his theory of the Forms. Plato explains that the world is divided into two realms, the
visible (which we grasp with our senses) and the intelligible (which we only grasp with
our mind). The visible world is the universe we see around us. The intelligible world is
comprised of the Formsabstract, changeless absolutes such as Goodness, Beauty,
Redness, and Sweetness that exist in permanent relation to the visible realm and make it
possible. (An apple is red and sweet, the theory goes, because it participates in the
Forms of Redness and Sweetness.) Only the Forms are objects of knowledge, because only
they possess the eternal unchanging truth that the mindnot the sensesmust
apprehend.
Only those whose minds are trained to grasp the
Formsthe philosopherscan know anything at all. In particular, what the
philosophers must know in order to become able rulers is the Form
of the Goodthe source of all other Forms, and of knowledge, truth,
and beauty. Plato cannot describe this Form
directly, but he claims that it is to the intelligible realm what the sun is to the
visible realm. Using the allegory of the cave, Plato paints an evocative portrait of the
philosophers soul moving through various stages of cognition (represented by the
line) through the visible realm into the intelligible, and finally grasping the Form of
the Good. The aim of education is not to put knowledge into the soul, but to put the right
desires into the soulto fill the soul with a lust for truth, so that it desires to
move past the visible world, into the intelligible, ultimately to the Form of the Good.
|
|
|
Sphinx grave stela -
Athens 535 B.C. |
Lion - Corinth, Greece
550 B.C. |
Philosophers
form the only class of people to possess knowledge and are also the most just people.
Their souls, more than others, aim to fulfil the desires of the rational part. After
comparing the philosopher king to the most unjust type of personrepresented by the
tyrant, who is ruled entirely by his non-rational appetitesPlato claims that justice
is worthwhile for its own sake. In Book IX he presents three arguments for the conclusion
that it is desirable to be just. By sketching a psychological portrait of the tyrant, he
attempts to prove that injustice tortures a persons psyche, whereas a just soul is a
healthy, happy one, untroubled and calm. Next he argues that, though each of the three
main character typesmoney-loving, honor-loving, and truth-lovinghave their own
conceptions of pleasure and of the corresponding good lifeeach choosing his own life
as the most pleasantonly the philosopher can judge because only he has experienced
all three types of pleasure. The others should accept the philosophers judgement and
conclude that the pleasures associated with the philosophical are most pleasant and thus
that the just life is also most pleasant. He tries to demonstrate that only philosophical
pleasure is really pleasure at all; all other pleasure is nothing more than cessation of
pain.
One might notice that none of these arguments actually
prove that justice is desirable apart from its consequencesinstead, they establish
that justice is always accompanied by true pleasure. In all probability, none of these is
actually supposed to serve as the main reason why justice is desirable. Instead, the
desirability of justice is likely connected to the intimate relationship between the just
life and the Forms. The just life is good in and of itself because it involves grasping
these ultimate goods, and imitating their order and harmony, thus incorporating them into
ones own life. Justice is good, in other words, because it is connected to the
greatest good, the Form of the Good.
Plato ends the Republic
on a surprising note. Having defined justice and established it as the greatest good, he
banishes poets from his city. Poets, he claims, appeal to the basest part of the soul by
imitating unjust inclinations. By encouraging us to indulge ignoble emotions in sympathy
with the characters we hear about, poetry encourages us to indulge these emotions in life.
Poetry, in sum, makes us unjust. In closing, Plato relates the myth of Er, which describes
the trajectory of a soul after death. Just souls are rewarded for one thousand lifetimes,
while unjust ones are punished for the same amount of time. Each soul then must choose its
next life. (Adapted from
Sparknotes.com)
Read: Republic Plato Book
X <http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/republic.11.x.html> |
~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~
Literature: Background:
Nearly three thousand years
after they were composed, the Iliad and
the Odyssey remain two of the most
celebrated and widely read stories ever told, yet next to nothing is known about their
composer. He was certainly an accomplished Greek bard, and he probably lived in the late
eighth and early seventh centuries b.c. Authorship is
traditionally ascribed to a blind poet named Homer, and it is under this name that the
works are still published. Greeks of the third and second centuries b.c., however, already questioned whether Homer existed and
whether the two epics were even written by a single individual.
Most modern scholars believe that even if a single person
wrote the epics, his work owed a tremendous debt to a long tradition of unwritten, oral
poetry. Stories of a glorious expedition to the East and of its leaders fateful
journeys home had been circulating in Greece for hundreds of years before the Iliad and Odyssey
were composed. Casual storytellers and semiprofessional minstrels passed these stories
down through generations, with each artist developing and polishing the story as he told
it. According to this theory, one poet, multiple poets working in collaboration, or
perhaps even a series of poets handing down their work in succession finally turned these
stories into written works, again with each adding his own touch and expanding or
contracting certain episodes in the overall narrative to fit his taste.
|
|
Reconstruction of
Homer's view of the world |
Although historical, archaeological, and linguistic evidence
suggests that the epics were composed between 750 and 650 b.c. they are set in
Mycenaean Greece in about the twelfth century b.c.,
during the Bronze Age. This earlier period, the Greeks believed, was a more glorious and
sublime age, when gods still frequented the earth and heroic, godlike mortals with
superhuman attributes populated Greece. Because the two epics strive to evoke this
pristine age, they are written in a high style and generally depict life as it was
believed to have been led in the great kingdoms of the Bronze Age. The Greeks are often
referred to as Achaeans, the name of a large tribe occupying Greece during the
Bronze Age.
But Homers reconstruction often yields to the
realities of eighth- and seventh-century b.c. Greece. The
feudal social structure apparent in the background of the Odyssey
seems more akin to Homers Greece than to Odysseuss, and Homer substitutes the
pantheon of deities of his own day for the related but different gods whom Mycenaean
Greeks worshipped. Many other minor but obvious anachronismssuch as references to
iron tools and to tribes that had not yet migrated to Greece by the Bronze Agebetray
the poems later, Iron Age origins.
For centuries, many scholars believed that the Trojan War
and its participants were entirely the creation of the Greek imagination. But in the late
nineteenth century, an archaeologist named Heinrich Schliemann declared that he had
discovered the remnants of Troy. The ruins that he uncovered sit a few dozen miles off of
the Aegean coast in northwestern Turkey, a site that indeed fits the geographical
descriptions of Homers Troy. One layer of the site, roughly corresponding to the
point in history when the fall of Troy would have taken place, shows evidence of fire and
destruction consistent with a sack. Although most scholars accept Schliemanns
discovered city as the site of the ancient city of Troy, many remain skeptical as to
whether Homers Trojan War ever really took place. Evidence from Near Eastern
literature suggests that episodes similar to those described in the Iliad may have circulated even before Schliemanns
Troy was destroyed. Nonetheless, many scholars now admit the possibility that some truth
may lie at the center of the Iliad, hidden beneath
many layers of poetic embellishment.
|
|
Troy -- east gate
(Early Bronze Age) |
|
Like the Odyssey, the Iliad was composed primarily in the Ionic dialect of
Ancient Greek, which was spoken on the Aegean islands and in the coastal settlements of
Asia Minor, now modern Turkey. Some scholars thus conclude that the poet hailed from
somewhere in the eastern Greek world. More likely, however, the poet chose the Ionic
dialect because he felt it to be more appropriate for the high style and grand scope of
his work. Slightly later Greek literature suggests that poets varied the dialects of their
poems according to the themes that they were treating and might write in dialects that
they didnt actually speak. Homers epics are Panhellenic (encompassing all of
Greece) in spirit and use forms from several other dialects. This suggests that Homer
suited his poems to the dialect that would best complement his ideas.
The Aftermath of the Iliad
The Trojan War has not yet ended
at the close of the Iliad. Homers audience
would have been familiar with the struggles conclusion, and the potency of much of
Homers irony and foreboding depends on this familiarity. What follows is a synopsis
of some of the most important events that happen after the Iliad
ends.
|
Achilles receiving
armor from Thetis |
In the final books of the Iliad,
Achilles refers frequently to his imminent death, about which his mother, Thetis,
has warned him. After the end of the poem, at Hectors funeral feast, Achilles sights
the beautiful Polyxena, the daughter of Priam and hence a princess of Troy. Taken with her
beauty, Achilles falls in love with her. Hoping to marry her, he agrees to use his
influence with the Achaean army to bring about an end to the war. But when he travels to
the temple of Apollo to negotiate the peace, Paris shoots him in the heelthe only
vulnerable part of his bodywith a poisoned arrow. In other versions of the story,
the wound occurs in the midst of battle.
After Achilles death, Ajax
and Odysseus go and recover his body. Thetis instructs the Achaeans to bequeath
Achilles magnificent armor, forged by the god Hephaestus, to the most worthy hero.
Both Ajax and Odysseus covet the armor; when it is awarded to Odysseus, Ajax commits
suicide out of humiliation.
The Palladium and
the Arrows of Heracles
By the time of Achilles and Ajaxs deaths,
Troys defenses have been bolstered by the arrival of a new coalition of allies,
including the Ethiopians and the Amazons. Achilles killed Penthesilea, the queen of the
Amazons, before his death, but the Trojans continue to repel the Achaean assault. The gods
relay to the Achaeans that they must perform a number of tasks in order to win the war:
they must recover the arrows of Heracles, steal a statue of Athena called the Palladium
from the temple in Troy, and perform various other challenges. Largely owing to the skill
and courage of Odysseus and Diomedes, the Achaeans accomplish the tasks, and the Achaean
archer Philoctetes later uses the arrows of Heracles to kill Paris. Despite this setback,
Troy continues to hold against the Achaeans.
|
Beware
of Greeks bearing gifts |
The Achaean commanders are nearly ready to give up;
nothing can penetrate the massive walls of Troy. But before they lose heart, Odysseus
concocts a plan that will allow them to bypass the walls of the city completely. The
Achaeans build a massive, hollow, wooden horse, large enough to hold a contingent of
warriors inside. Odysseus and a group of soldiers hide in the horse, while the rest of the
Achaeans burn their camps and sail away from Troy, waiting in their ships behind a nearby
island.
The next morning, the Trojans peer down from the ramparts
of their wall and discover the gigantic, mysterious horse. They also discover a lone
Achaean soldier named Sinon, whom they take prisoner. As instructed by Odysseus, Sinon
tells the Trojans that the Achaeans have incurred the wrath of Athena for the theft of the
Palladium. They have left Sinon as a sacrifice to the goddess and constructed the horse as
a gift to soothe her temper. Sinon explains that the Achaeans left the horse before the
Trojan gates in the hopes that the Trojans would destroy it and thereby earn the wrath of
Athena.
Believing Sinons story, the Trojans wheel the
massive horse into the city as a tribute to Athena. That night, Odysseus and his men slip
out of the horse, kill the Trojan guards, and fling open the gates of Troy to the Achaean
army, which has meanwhile approached the city again. Having at last penetrated the wall,
the Achaeans massacre the citizens of Troy, plunder the citys riches, and burn the
buildings to the ground. All of the Trojan men are killed except for a small group led by
Aeneas, who escapes. Helen, whose loyalties have shifted back to the Achaeans since
Pariss death, returns to Menelaus, and the Achaeans at last set sail for home.
The fates of many of the Iliads
heroes after the war occupy an important space in Greek mythology. Odysseus, as foretold,
spends ten years trying to return to Ithaca, and his adventures form the subject of
Homers other great epic, the Odyssey. Helen
and Menelaus have a long and dangerous voyage back to their home in Sparta, with a long
stay in Egypt. In the Odyssey, Telemachus travels
to Sparta in search of his father, Odysseus, and finds Helen and Menelaus celebrating the
marriage of their daughter, Hermione. Agamemnon, who has taken Priams daughter
Cassandra as a slave, returns home to his wife, Clytemnestra, and his kingdom, Mycenae.
Ever since Agamemnons sacrifice of Iphigeneia at the altar of Athena, however,
Clytemnestra has nurtured a vast resentment toward her husband. She has taken a man named
Aegisthus as her lover, and upon Agamemnons return, the lovers murder Agamemnon in
his bath and kill Cassandra as well. This story is the subject of Aeschyluss play Agamemnon. Meanwhile, Aeneas, the only great Trojan
warrior to survive the fall of Troy, wanders for many years, searching for a new home for
his surviving fellow citizens. His adventures are recounted in Virgils epic Aeneid. (Adapted from Sparknotes.com)
Read: The Iliad Homer Book
19 <http://www.mala.bc.ca/~johnstoi/homer/iliad19.htm>
Reference pages:
Please go the Discussion
for Week 2 (Discuss-2)
|