BUT WHAT ABOUT AESTHETICS?
As mentioned earlier, there are many groups opposed to employing Jungian typology
or the MBTI because they fear it may encourage people to see other human beings in terms
of stereotypes. Many people also do not like
the idea of thinking of themselves as falling neatly into categories; they feel human
beings are much more complex than belonging to one of only sixteen types. At this point it might be worthwhile to remind
them that this is theory and not a practical resource meant for application in
the classroom or anywhere else. As Dr.
Mamchur and others have said, typology is a tool, something that can aid us in
finding a starting point where we may begin to conceive of the diversity of personality in
human beings. The MBTI categories are
acknowledged as very broad designations and only indicate patterns of preferences
in how we perceive the world and judge situations in order to make decisions.
The artists themselves are the most
resistant to applying any kind of a science or system in relation to creativity and
especially the arts. I would agree that the
artist needs absolute freedom when approaching her work and is doomed if she tries to
hitch her artistic skills to a framework as she begins to create. Aesthetics and the creative process, by the nature
of their being, cannot accept any limiting or overlaying guidelines. As Collingwood puts it, how can a writer know what
shes going to write until shes written it?
It is the quintessential organic process and the artist only finds out what
she is going to create as she is in the throes of creating it.
Personally, Ive struggled with the
idea that typology might be a better way to look at personalities. I have felt myself go through distinct stages. First, being very curious about the qualities of
the four preferences, pairs and sixteen types and have delighted in class when we point
out examples of acting our type. Second,
I felt myself enter a fatigue stage, where I became tired of thinking of
people along the lines of type and wanted to go back to my old, more natural
way of seeing people. Third, after two years
of not working with type and deciding to enroll in this course which would be fully
dedicated to type, I felt both intrigued and cautious intrigued because I had done
a lot more fiction writing in the meantime and wanted to improve my ability to create
literary characters, but cautious because I had become much more aware of the organic
nature of writing and had settled on my own method of writing, which I realized had been
evolving ever since childhood. Lastly, the
stage which I am in now (!) seems to be more in harmony with Hegelian logic: thesis + antithesis = synthesis. That is, I see the value of type plus its negative
aspects or limitations and yet I can use it as a tool along with my other tools, so that I
take from type what I want and use it to help my writing in the way I choose.
Mainly the benefit I gain from using
typology in writing is not in the creative process, but in the editing process. After I have been free to let my imagination roam
and begun to gather ideas, after Ive scratched out a first draft and played with the
characters and conflicts until something begins to coalesce, and not until Ive got a
solid piece of work then I am able to isolate my characters and compare their
behavior to the established behavior patterns of the functions. I remind myself that some characters are hard to
type and not all will need to fit into the sixteen types.
But perhaps typology is most helpful in the editing stage when I look at two
characters who are in conflict. Often it is
when functions are opposed that more of their differences can be brought out in high
relief. Knowing what their shadows will be in
crisis also helps determine their behavior at the climax.
Finally, I feel that learning about type
helps me most as a writer in terms of self-development.
Being more aware of my own type can direct me to focus on my weaker areas. For example, as a dominant N, I know that I should
make a conscious effort to take the time to add enough detail to my writing, especially to
take care about writing in more scenic time or including more sensuous description. This has often been mentioned in feedback from
other writers, and knowing now about my type, this makes perfect sense.
There is one area of type Ive been
saving for last and that is the Shadow. But
before I cover that area, Id like to return to the idea of aesthetics in more
detail. Many thinkers have written about this
subject as it relates to the functions, in particular thinking and feeling, and I would
like to bring them into the discussion now.
(Barber,
April 2005)
Aesthetics
Art is often defined simply as
expression. Lyas (103) qualifies
that by emphasizing it is the degree of expression.
Within that, there are two kinds of expression, ordinary and artistic. The latter must have two qualities to render it
art. First, sufficiency, wherein
the work has a greater intensity and range than the ordinary, and second, a
necessity. It is not just the
sound of birds singing that makes music, but a complex kind of making of sounds. And in this, the artists personality comes
through. (98-102).
Art is expression then, but we must also
understand how it is expressed. And we might
add that art is powerful because of the expressive significance of representation. (56).
All of these ideas come under the umbrella term
aesthetics. A somewhat slippery word,
it refers to a branch of philosophy dealing with the nature and perception of what is
beautiful, and includes taste or the appreciation of beauty. Here we are most concerned with aestheticism,
the idea that beauty may be the basic principle from which all other principles,
especially moral principles, are derived.
Abbs (3) states that the aesthetic is a mode of
intelligence. Just as a deductive method of
conceptual thinking is developed through logic, mathematics, dialectical and analytical
philosophy, the aesthetic uses not concepts but percepts of sensory
experience. The arts become symbolic forms
for what they wish to communicate. There is a
continuum here, a sliding scale between sensation and feeling, of sensory experience and
sensibility. When we touch an object, we have
a perceptual experience, while to be touched is to be moved emotionally. We can say then that the aesthetic includes both
the perceptual and the affective. Growing in
aesthetic intelligence therefore deals with the development of sensation and feeling into
what adds up to be a whole greater than its parts, a sensibility. (4).
The point we are leading up to is that
aesthetic intelligence, when defined in this way, is particular to the arts. It is true, that although there can be feelings of
beauty in response to a scientific discovery or a mathematical proof, what I want to focus
on, here and in this thesis, is a method of responding that is inherent in human life and
one that can only be accessed through senses and feelings.
It is not so much the actual sensation that is valued but the apprehension
that derives from it. (6). Therefore,
returning to Abbss (7) definition, the artist can be said to be a perceptual
philosopher, one who seeks through the symbolic ordering of her sensations a means
to gain understanding of the human experience.
It was Kant who put aesthetics at the center of
philosophy. (Scruton 26). In the Critique
of Judgment, Kant places the aesthetic experience in a similar category as the
religious experience by suggesting it is the former and not the latter that is the
archetype of revelation. Specifically, what
he is saying is that the aesthetic experience is able to reveal the sense of the world. How does this happen? Simply, in the presence of beauty an individual
senses the purposiveness and intelligibility in the things around him. This beauty may be highly subjective to the
individual or it may be his recognition of what is beautiful based on what has been
culturally transmitted to him.
Either way, when we apprehend the sublime, we
feel as though we can see beyond the world to something overwhelming, ineffable and yet
strangely grounded. Scruton (26) states that
formerly it was the traditional concern of theology to provide a greater meaning of the
world, but even before Kant, this faculty which has beauty as its goal, was the same thing
as aesthetic contemplation. Scruton further
states that human beings have always had intimations of the transcendental,
either personal or cultural, as a quality of being human.
None of this can be argued fully with reason.
Language has its limits here. As
we try to grope our way between thought and emotion we become intuitive rather than
rational or analytical. This is because we
are able to grasp the idea of the transcendental without being able to verbalize it. Ultimately we know nothing of the transcendental. But we feel it and it is in this feeling of
beauty that we sense truth. (26).
To take this idea further, we could say that
when we become aware of the beauty in a literary work, its content begins to feel true. And simultaneously, as we start to become
conscious of the literary world presented to us, certain truths about that
world begin to emerge. We might even believe
that these truths make perfect sense, within that world. This is remarkably so in the case of inspired
religious texts, where apprehension of these works beauty, and therefore feelings of
truth, inexplicably begins to intimate at meaning.
This may seem to be a non sequitur where
beautiful but different works of art both present the truth despite the
contradictory nature of their content. Murdoch
(8) explains that unlike philosophy and science, literature asks us to submit
oneself to criteria outside oneself; (the author) tries to say something that is impersonally
true. I feel the answer lies
somehow closer to Aristotles concept, that just as we learn to value individuals
within their qualitatively distinct situations, we must also consider works of literature
within the contexts of their unique worlds and therefore examine the truth
found therein. Therefore, there may be no
absolute truths to be found in any one work of literature in relation to the
real world; too much depends upon the circumstances presented in the story and
also on the life, experiences and views of the reader, or, even more specifically, what
that reader believes to be true, both subjectively as well as culturally, religiously,
etc. Even scientific truths have been proven
false since the time they were included in classical works.
What we can say with some certainty is that taken collectively, there are
norms of morality that emerge from a survey of the literary canon, which may
point at general truths.
Returning now to Kants third Critique, we
see the significance of the shift from religion to philosophy, specifically Christianity
to the Enlightenment, which was to bring ethics and aesthetics to the forefront. Echoing the Copernican revolution in science, Kant
believes the mind gives structure to the world and not the other way round. What occurs, he says, is that we struggle to
organize the bombardment of random stimuli into perceived objects, which is done by our
imagination. The creation of conceptual
categories is done through understanding. (Lyas
25). What we have when the mind plays back
and forth between imagination and understanding is aesthetic delight or rapture. (31). This takes place in a state of disinterestedness,
when there is no personal motivation for assigning value.
(28). It is often called an
aesthetic attitude, or a possession of a psychic distance, that allows the mind to roam
with controlled imagination. The freedom that
ensues releases us from the numbness of our daily lives. (31).
This is why we are so attracted to art and why
it is so powerful to us. (19). We stand in
awe before representation and tend to cherish those works by gifted artists who are able
to capture a part of life and truth. (38).
Through its unique blend of form and content,
then, art can remind us of our humanity in new and fresh ways and confirm our
connectedness to others. It says a great deal
about the permanence of values and conceptions of human nature that startles us when we
realize we can still understand Homer and Aeschylus.
Literature is the main vehicle, as it was in Homers time, for this
wide-ranging understanding. We would not want
to be cut off from this vast encyclopedia of the past, in terms of its art, history or
moral viewpoints. (Murdoch 25).
|
Magic Eye --
What do you see in the picture? |
Collingwood and The Principles of Art
Collingwood (15) goes to great lengths to
define what art is not, and why. Art,
he tells us, is not craft, mainly because it cannot have an end in mind when the artist is
at the beginning. How does the author know
what a story is about until she has written it? Art
is not representational, in that it does not copy another work of art or real life
situations. Imitation is impossible in
storytelling anyway because if the writer changes one thing it becomes a completely
different work of art. A true imitation would
be the identical story. Further, an author
trying to recreate a real event from life would find it impossible to include
every visual detail, every personality trait and point of view without sacrificing the
story.
Plato believed all art was representational and therefore too removed from reality
to convey the truth. But Collingwood
disagrees; he says art may be representational but what makes it a work of art proper is
another thing what is missing is the emotional aspect, as we shall see. We might, however, acknowledge that Plato was on
to something, and although he did not have the concept of aesthetics in his day, he
criticized art in a way that echoes the publics view of art, which tends to see art
as mere entertainment or distraction. It is
well known that Plato banished the poets from his ideal republic because he objected to
the emotion that was stimulated by art, which in his view clouded the rational mind. What may have been further behind this is that in
Platos era there was a shift in ancient Greeces values. As Greece began to dominate the region in
ideologies, religion, philosophy, politics and economics, the religious-based art of
pre-Socratic times began to evolve from what Collingwood terms magical art, or
art with a purpose, to one of a more trivial nature, amusement art. Whereas in the earlier times people used art to
instill religious values, good behavior and noble deeds, now people were attending theatre
performances to be entertained and to let off tensions through tragedy or comedy.
Aristotle, on the other hand, defended Greek
drama as being useful, and maintained that by arousing dangerous emotions in a controlled
setting, the play was facilitating catharsis, or release of pent up emotions,
which served a purpose in society. Plato
might have disagreed, saying the opposite is more likely to occur just as we see in our
own times with copycat crimes. The
teenage boys who gunned down their fellow students at Columbine had supposedly just
watched an extreme example of glorified violence in The Matrix.
Art then for the ancient Greeks was
craft, created with an end in mind. The
aim was to entertain the masses and Plato objected most to its irrational, trivial nature. Plato wrote the Republic to warn of the
dangers facing a society that is given over more and more to amusement, and also to the
citizens who feel because there is less meaning in life they must reach out for
distractions. He went as far as to say that
the percentage of a societys citizens who pursue pleasure is directly related to the
health of its civilization.
If this conception of art is accurate, we
may well ask what this bodes for our times. Platos
solution was to remove art in order to promote truth and rationality in the ideal
republic. We must hold close to
Aristotles view of ethics to find more appreciation of the arts in terms of its
virtue, justice, pleasure, honor and the good it can bring.
Before we move on, however, one last but important distinction must be made here
between Platos condemnation of amusement art and the perfect refutation of that view
in the example of hybridization in Shakespeare. Here
we find the answer to Platos blanket dismissal.
Keenly aware that his livelihood depended on enthralling the masses, Shakespeare
nonetheless applied his unique abilities to raising art above amusement to art
proper, by adding emotional complexity and rational contemplation on multiple levels
of understanding. His plays appealed to the
groundlings up to the royal boxes and here we have proof that art can be many things at
once.
Returning to our definition of art, which Collingwood has labeled not as craft,
magic or amusement, we must now ask, what is art proper? Genuine art, Collingwood tell us, is about
expressing emotion. The act of expressing
it, in the process of making the work, is an exploration of the artists emotion. It cannot be crafted because the artist does not
yet know what the emotion is because she has not yet expressed it. Along with this is the idea that it cannot be
technique; if a writer describes an emotion, it is no longer expressed. The beginning writer is exhorted: Show! Dont
tell. Many authors have slipped in their art
because they were lazy or somehow believed the message would not get through. This is the case at the end of Crime and
Punishment, when Dostoyevsky cannot refrain from resorting to direct statements about
the characters situation and the implications for humanity. Ironically, he must have felt the whole novel
previous to this did not say the same thing and the poet in Dostoyevsky yielded to the
philosopher. (Cutler 3). As a result, the astute reader feels hit over the
head with the redundancy and the imaginative aesthetic experience is greatly diminished.
Coleridge may have said it best when he claimed to identify a poet by the fact that
as the poet was expressing his emotions he was enabling us to express our own.
It may be the case that not all artists are willing to do the hard labor that is
required to create art proper. For it is true
that it is much more difficult to read, and therefore write, literature proper. Non-fiction not only tells us what to think, it
tells us how to think about its subject. All
the hard work is done for us in reading non-fiction.
It is presented in a clear, rational, journalistic style and leaves no doubt to
meaning that is, what it means to the author.
The authorial voice is firmly in place. If
we choose, we never have to search for our own meaning.
But, we can relax; just accept what we read as the truth. Somebody elses truth.
In sharp contrast, literature that challenges us to find out who we are and what we
think helps us in the world. This is the
essence of the aesthetic experience. Put
simply, good art is good for us.
Putting Feeling to Work in Aesthetics
Perhaps we need to go a bit deeper beyond
the meaning of art proper to the artist. Who
must the artist be in order to produce a significant work of art? Collingwood (279) cites the necessity of deep and
powerful emotions, and Coleridge describes the poet as someone who must feel deeply before
he can think deeply. But the artist is not
the genius of the Romantic era who is endowed with special powers, or
Platos concept of the mad or irrational poet who serves as a conduit of
the gods. Collingwood (119) says the artist
is one who solves the problem of how to express emotion and thereby leads the reader to
his own expression.
In The Principles of Art, Collingwood
painstakingly outlines his theory of the role emotions play in our aesthetic response. He suggests that phenomenon bombard us
with stimuli which reach us through the senses. Each
sensum we receive comes with an emotional charge, which are inseparable at the
psychical level, below our awareness. As our
attention shifts and we notice a particular sensum-emotion, we become conscious of
receiving it. For example, waves of sound
move into our ear as mere noise, simultaneously high-pitched and tense, a
sensum and an emotion. When we become
conscious of it, our field of awareness splits into hearing the sound, noticing it and
then naming it as high-pitched and tense as we seek to dominate it as an idea
in our imagination. Our attention
now focuses on this one thing in exclusion to others.
Here in the conscious imagination we decide what we feel about it, then
begin to make connections or relations with other ideas.
It now moves into the realm of the intellect.
But this is not all of it. When a writer creates a story, it may only exist
in her mind. (Collingwood 131). If she puts it down on paper, it is only black
symbols on a white page, or groups of letters strung across paper. The artists goal is to bring the story into
existence as she feels and sees in her head. The
words on the page are at this point only the means by which the reader, if he reads
intelligently, can reconstruct for himself the story that existed in the authors
mind at the time of writing. (139). For it is true that unless the reader begins to
hear the words, even silently inside his head, take them as his own, respond
to the rhyme and rhythm, pattern and intonation, as well as falling in with the
authors particular use of language and begin to recognize the effect of this
language to reproduce emotion, then the work will remain nothing but ink prints on white
paper.
However, if the author has through symbol,
language and sound put an emotional experience in motion, and if the readers
imagination is able to fill in all the spaces around these symbols to flesh out the
experience, then the minds eye of the reader begins to see a whole world there,
which adds up to much more that ink or words.
It is these very areas of indeterminacy that
are the most fundamental elements of aesthetic response.
The gaps invite engagement and participation. (Iser). But again, we have to make the effort. If the author evokes enough vivid points of
reference, say, in describing the rumbling of canons along a gutted road, cries coming
from the trees and smoke reddening an already bloody sunset, then a powerful emotional
response begins to coalesce, as well as a fuller picture of a world beyond
what we are told. This is how we can feel we
have been present at the Battle of Borodino; the experience of reading War and Peace
is that immediate. Tolstoy has provided the
first part; that of translating his own aesthetic experience into words that would make a
sensum-emotional impression upon our consciousness so that we as readers could
imaginatively reconstruct it in our own minds. This
is not to say that we focus only on the sensuous part and put our imagination to work; we
are able to find impressions because we are utilizing our imaginative powers to discover
what the author would like to reveal. Collingwood
(151) describes this as an imaginary experience of total activity which we find (in
the work of art) because (the artist) had put it there. The work of art proper is a total activity
which the person enjoying it apprehends, or is conscious of by the use of his
imagination.
The artist is not aiming to produce a
preconceived emotional effect in the reader; the author is exploring her own emotions
(122). The only aim at the beginning of
creating a work is to discover emotions in herself as related to a subject, characters, or
situation, etc., that she was previously unaware of.
By sharing with the reader the process by which she discovered them she
enables the reader to a) witness the discovery, and b) enable the reader to make a similar
discovery in himself. Again, this is not done
by direct statements in literature or by telling the reader what to think. This is key to understanding how ethics and
aesthetics are united in art.
Truth in the Artist
It is often said that a writer writes because she must. Something within her compels her to write a
certain story. She is in need of exploring a
particular set of circumstances, and of all the possibilities, she has chosen this one. Collingwood (287) says that each (work of
art) is created to express an emotion arising within (the artist) at that point in his
life and no other
and if the generative act which produces that utterance is an act
of consciousness, and hence an act of thought, it follows that this utterance, so far from
being indifferent to the distinction between truth and falsehood, is necessarily an
attempt to state the truth. So far as the
utterance is a good work of art, it is a true utterance; its artistic merit and its truth
are the same thing.
It is precisely in this struggle to discover and convey deep, authentic emotion
that leads to creating significant art, and holds the potential of being called
good art. Collingwood (291) says,
the artist is a person who comes to know himself, to know his emotion
this
knowing of himself is a making of himself. In
other words, the work that she creates at this particular time is personally true for this
artist.
To define a thing implies there could be a
good thing of that kind (280). To call
things (such as art) good and bad is to imply success and failure. For Collingwood, it follows then that a work of
art may be either good or bad, but a bad work of art might be due to an unsuccessful
attempt at becoming conscious of a given emotion. If
this fault lies within the artist, it could be construed in a number of ways. The writer may weakly express an emotion, as
weve said, and just tell it. Or,
she could avoid it altogether, misread it, or blunder through it. But in the way it relates to our problem, it seems
to be a case of disguising it from herself. This
might be caused by denying to herself that it exists, or that it is not her own emotion
but coming from something else. Collingwood
(282) says this choice occurs in the level of awareness just before consciousness -- earlier would be too soon for awareness; later
would be to tell oneself a lie, since if she were conscious of the truth she could not
deceive herself about it. Therefore, it is on
the border of the psychical level and conscious level.
It is the malperformance of the act which converts what is merely
psychical (impression) into what is conscious (idea) which leads to a
corruption of consciousness.
Often this very corruption of consciousness, caused by a failure to express an
emotion, is what prevents the writer from realizing whether the emotion has been expressed
or not. It is a veritable circle a bad
artist is a bad judge of her own art (283). But
Collingwood generously states that no ones consciousness is completely corrupted
it is often partial or temporary and that is why at other times the writer
is able to judge the success of her own work and realize when it is not working. In fact, most experienced authors are constantly
on guard to eliminate these corruptions. What
is of danger, as we have implied above, is when instead of expressing emotions, the artist
disowns them or intentionally avoids facing the truth of them. If the author wishes to remain ignorant of
emotions that terrify or disgust, for example, then this is not only bad art but damaging
art. (284). How this occurs we shall show in
later sections.
The Good in the Artist
If the artist has two goals, first to become
more in touch with a greater range and depth of emotions (imagination), and secondly, to
improve her ability to express those emotions through her art (skills), then how might she
go about this? If good art is
expressing emotions successfully, then does it follow that a good writer would
be more successful at discovering emotions within herself?
How would someone improve their ability to discover emotions? I think we might say it comes back to the idea of
being attentive to the emotional truth within oneself and working hard to avoid a
corruption of consciousness. But we are still
too limited in ourselves and our lives to have experiences which might lead to discovering
a greater range and depth of emotion. Granted,
some authors have made careers of going over and over the same territory, ever deepening
their own understanding of their obsessions, such as Fitzgerald and Munro. But even they had to have exposure to other forms
of these experiences and emotions in order to grow. The
obvious answer here is to read other successful literature.
One of the main ways that
literature is unique, as Aristotle says, is that it ushers us into a larger life; without
it we have not lived enough to escape the confines of our parochial existence. (Nussbaum 47).
Also, because we engage with literature in a disinterested manner, we are
able to get close enough to watch and begin to understand the other. There is irony here; while recognizing the
strangeness of others, literature invites us to withhold judgment until we have discerned
the separate and qualitative uniqueness of other beings.
After we have opened ourselves up, we have a chance to see ourselves in
them. It allows us to perceive beyond
ourselves. Then the
otherness which enters into us makes us other. (Steiner 188).
The challenge is to let go ourselves in order to become something better, as
writers, readers or human beings.
As the author becomes more adept at determining the
truth in emotions, she more easily discerns what is good art. But how is the artist to find what is good in
herself? There is no formula for developing
the virtues of being a writer, but the artist can subject herself to self-examination to
determine the truthfulness of her consciousness. And
yet writing is such a solitary act. A writer
needs readers, but even then there is little direct response in the same way that an actor
has an audience. For writers it is important
to have the feedback of other writers, for support as well as criticism. The literary critic comes too late for the author;
it is during the process of writing that a response is needed. The place where much valuable collaboration occurs
is in the creative writing classroom.
The Authors True Personality (The Only Author We Can Really Know)
In literature, the identification of the
posited author is most critical to student learning. By posited I mean not a character in
the story who might seem to represent the authors viewpoint, or even the narrator,
who appears to be leading the reader through the story and pointing at things to notice. Nor do I mean the historical author, the man
Melville or the woman Virginia Woolf. We can
know little about what they as people really thought about savages sailing on
whaling boats or how lonely professors wives felt.
Precisely then, the posited author is the controlling intelligence of the story,
the emotional-thinking being who created the story in her imagination through an emotional
discovery and decided this result was what best expressed meaning for her. Shakespeare could have had a bit of Edmund in
him, or saw himself as King Lear in his own life, but he is not saying, I am an
existentialist, or, Kings should rule until their death, as his overall
message to the reader. These ideas may be
imagined by the reader because Shakespeares characters felt them from their position
in their worlds. But Shakespeare
as posited author had a much more complex intention in mind for us as readers. The effect in the last scene in King Lear
when the beaten king carries on stage the lifeless body of his daughter is impossible to
render in words. The audience is left to work
through issues of being and existence raised to new levels of consciousness.
Devereaux (7) says, Our access to the posited author is secured through the
act of interpretation
As readers, however, the primary object of our attention is
not the pages the ink on paper but the story. To make sense of such judgments we must consider
the narrative from the standpoint of the reader. Seen
from that standpoint, the posited author becomes intelligible. We read under the concept of literary
purposiveness. Therefore,
we can dispute whether The Merchant of Venice criticizes, endorses, or merely
investigates the idea of moral payment embodied in Shylocks pound of
flesh. The evidence for our judgments
about the posited author will consist in texts and the reading of texts. In the end, moral judgments about the
literary work itself are not determining who the real life person was, but in interpreting
the emotional viewpoint of the posited author.
When students learn about their own authorial voice as posited author they see
their vision from a distance. Beyond this,
they recognize the quality of their own aesthetic experience as writers. They begin to engage with truth in emotion and
the ideas in stories and gain experience and maturity as writers and as persons. The focus moves towards elucidating their
understanding of humanity and existence. That
life is not rational becomes clear and soon they grasp that some truths just cannot be
learned through rational methods. Heidegger
states that there is a fundamental way of being that is not cognitive. In fact, it is the mirror image of
Descartess famous phrase, cogito sum ergo. It comes down to being instead of
knowing, and not the reverse. What
we see at the end of King Lear is about being in the world. (Pike 26). We
see the same thing in our experience of T.S. Eliots poem, The Waste
Land. There is a resistance to having
it explained by another reader because we just want to be in the experience. The poem eludes explication anyway, and any
attempt will fail to capture its entirety. It
is best left as art to express its own meaning.
Knowledge in Art
Knowledge in art, Collingwood (289) tells us, is knowledge of the individual. Because the writer or thoughtful reader has
developed the habits of mind that allow her to think and feel for herself, she
automatically weighs the quality of her own aesthetic experience while engaging with the
art and compares the authors ethics with her own personal ethics.
Because literature does not tell us directly what to think and feel, the reader is
imagining what the authors words mean through a unique way of experiencing. Each reader has his own memories, way of assigning
emotion to sensum, making intellectual associations and in the end, his overall reactions
will be specific. And here is the great
paradox of literature: it is both specific and universal.
No one readers interpretation of a novel will be identical to another
readers, nor to the writers. One
example of this is how different the picture we have in our head of a novel is compared to
the film version we view in the theatre. We
are shocked to see how the director or producers have portrayed the
characters, setting, etc. It just
doesnt match how we have envisioned it. And
yet, how could it? Imagination varies between
individuals.
On another level, we are also in the habit of judging
the authors moral sensibility. When
concepts dont match our own, flags come up, which say, this doesnt make sense
to my worldview; or, it is unjust or plain wrong. If
enough flags are lifted, we begin to doubt the narrator; when there seems to be no purpose
to have an unreliable narrator, we call the posited author into question. Because we are thinking and feeling for ourselves,
and therefore using our moral imagination as Nussbaum (162) calls it, we move
into a more critical stance.
I must clarify here the difference between a character who is immoral and the
faulty consciousness of the author. As
mentioned before, authors often use evil characters for a purpose; they have a
role to play in driving the plot forward. Iago,
for instance, the most cunning of villains, teaches us about the folly of pride and
gullibility by the way he manipulates Othello. Shakespeare
as posited author is not condoning people who train on other peoples weaknesses to
advance their own designs. On the other hand,
had Shakespeare made Iago a general after Othellos death and celebrated his triumph,
we as sharp readers would shake our heads in confusion.
This ending would not fit our picture of the cosmos and our moral
imaginations cannot resolve the intentions behind such an outcome.
In summarizing our point for this section then, we might say that an interpretation
of the actual Othello will be slightly different for each person, depending on who
they are, their circumstances in life and so on, but the overall experience could be said
to be universal due to the plays archetypes and themes. In this way, the knowledge we acquire after
spending time with literature is both specific for the individual as well as universal in
terms of humanity and existence. The
aesthetic experience, therefore, as a matter of course, delivers us into a moral universe
where ethics emerge as a natural part of engaging with the art.
Ethics and Aesthetics as One in Literature
In this essay I have assumed there is an interplay between reading and writing and
have written elsewhere about why literature matters more to students who are creative
writers (Barber 2004). I would now like to
emphasize that the same interplay exists between ethics and aesthetics at the deepest
level of reading and writing.
Writers and readers have a moral responsibility to use the aesthetic experience to
verify ethics. Only a deep and prolonged
engagement with art will yield emotional truths and therefore confirm or deny the moral
health of each posited writer the reader encounters.
In Heideggers words, Art is truth setting itself to work.
Students need to be encouraged to develop the habit of engaging with literature,
not only because they need to discern what is quality art but also to exercise their moral
imaginations. For we have recognized the
dangers of a corrupt consciousness that senses the truth but turns away from it, denies it
and eventually represses it. The corrupt
consciousness prefers fantasies because it cannot dominate the impression and shrinks from
the effort. But the feeling from which
attention is distracted does not disappear; it infects the imagination to the extent that
the idea must be blamed on others, cast off or suppressed.
Collingwood (217-220) condemns the condition of a corrupt consciousness not only as
an untruth but as an example of evil. The
mind that refuses to face down this evil has delivered itself into the power of its
feelings.
What happens when a person, a society or even a whole civilization prefers
fantasies? Or, specifically, prefers the
fantasies promoted by newspapers, television newscasters or even government propaganda
departments? Taylors (9) third
malaise suggests the outcome: a
loss of freedom. When people choose the
pleasures of staying home, watching trivial entertainment and enjoying the
satisfactions of private life, as long as the government of the day produces the means to
these satisfactions
the future may hold a new kind of tyranny where leaders
appear mild and paternalistic but in fact hide a soft despotism
over which people will have little control. Contrasted
with recent political events in the world, Taylors prediction appears prescient.
However, Taylor (32) is not a pessimist, and he believes the remedy for the
malaises is to be found in art and what is most basic to human life: its fundamentally
dialogical character. When we come to
understand what it is to define ourselves
we see that we take as background some
sense of what is significant. In the
shadow of the malaises, I believe the art of teaching now demands a more active pursuit of
the virtues -- more courage to resist
instrumental reasoning, more honouring the slow process of emerging consciousness, more
justice and perhaps more righteous indignation. For
it is true that the teacher is an artist with an ethical awareness, whose business is
nothing less than to teach artistic excellence as well as the meaning of life. (excerpt from Barber, Susan. The
Ethics and Aesthetics of Literature Dec.2004) |