Walking on Two Legs: On The Very Possibility Ian Angus
I One of the figures often mentioned in this context, but rarely investigated in any detail, was Herbert Marcuse. His early association with Heidegger, the shift to the Frankfurt Schools critical theory of society, and his later notoriety as the guru of the New Left made him seem a protean, if not ecclectic, figure. Many studies of Marcuse have appeared over the intevening years and several of his students have tried to carry his ideas forward, but until now no systematic study of Marcuse has addressed his role in the relationship between Heideggerian phenomenology and Marxism. Andrew Feenbergs book Heidegger and Marcuse does exactly that and it does it brilliantly. Moreover, it is concerned not only with the history of ideas whereby phenomenology was supplanted by critical Marxism in Marcuses development, nor the continuing subterranean influence of phenomenology in his later work, but mainly with the philosophical question of the adequacy of a (Heideggerian) phenomenological Marxism as such, and the political question of the pertinence of such a philosophy to the conflicts and absences of our own time. Feenbergs book uses the history of ideas as its spine, with chapters on Heideggers accounting with Plato and Aristotle in the 1920s (when Marcuse was preparing his dissertation under Heideggers direction), Heideggers later development (especially the 1954 essay The Question Concerning Technology), Marcuses turn to Hegel in his dissertation and the later book on Hegel Reason and Revolution, the influence of Georg Lukács on Marcuse, and concludes with two chapters analyzing aesthetic redemption and the question concerning nature in Marcuses later, post-World War II, work. It is a thorough, detailed and rich history which allows Feenberg to make his philosophical and political arguments in the context of an appreciation and critique of Marcuses work. The most broad basis for comparison between Heidegger and Marx is their critique of modernity (also known as capitalism). The Marxism of the 1920s had discovered a problem with Marxs dialectic of subject and object that underwrites the anticipated reversal of alienation. This dialectic was intended to unite the objective critique of capitalist industry and economy with subjective revolutionary will, but history had by then shown that Marxs synthesis had, against its intentions, remained merely theoretical. Continuing crises of the capitalist economy not only did not provoke revolutionary consciousness but more often produced a turn to the Right against what Marxists called the objective interests of the working class. Marxist philosophers had to address the historical divergence of subject and object within a theoretical resolution of their relationship. It is for this that Marcuse turned to Heidegger. He thought that Heideggers concrete phenomenology of human practice (Dasein) could fill the absence in Marxist theory. Not that Marxist theory could take over Heideggerian phenomenology entirely unaltered. In order to fill out the abstract nature of Heideggers account of Dasein, Marcuse interpreted it more socially in terms of class and more historically in terms of the master-slave dialectic (80-1). Even much later, Feenberg argues, a Marcusian concept such as solidarity can be seen as a concretion of Heideggers concept of authenticity (93). Marcuses dissertation, written under Heideggers direction and later published as Hegels Ontology and the Theory of Historicity, aimed at this re-jigging through the concept of life. Feenberg claims that this text must be read with an eye to its strategies and absencesa position to which anyone who has written a dissertation will have some sympathy. It doesnt mention Heidegger or Dasein, though the word ontology in the title is a clue to its inspiration and the use of the term life goes back to Diltheys term that influenced Heidegger (51). The dissertation ended Marcuses apprenticeship with Heidegger and presciently introduced Hegel to provide the missing historical and social concreteness and well as serve as a code word for Marxism (68). The dissertation thus opened the door to Marcuses shift to the Frankfurt School and the increasing influence of Hegel, Freud and art to express the synthesis of subject and object in a tensional and kinetic concept of life. For Marcuse, this ended his turn to phenomenology, although, as Feenberg shows, its influence persisted in an underground fashion. One-Dimensional Man can be properly understood only as a Marxist response to Heideggers The Question Concerning Technology, an influence that is much more pervasive than the single reference would suggest since it supports Marcuses key concept of a technological a priori.3 Despite his key revisions intended to bring Heideggers phenomenology of human practice closer to a Marxist emphasis on society and class, Marcuse came to the conclusion that it was necessary to abandon the attempt to synthesize phenomenology and Marxism. This much was apparent as early as Hegels Ontology and the Theory of Historicity. Feenberg takes considerable care to unravel the Heideggerian and Hegelian threads in this text, concerned as he is to maintain that it represents neither a straightforward abandonment of phenomenology for Hegelian Marxism (against Marcuses self-interpretation and as Marxist accounts often claim) nor a simple maintenance of an untransformed Heideggerian Dasein analysis. The point of connection between these two threads is, as Lucien Goldmann has already shown,4 the 20th century philosophical project shared by Heidegger and Lukács to address the crisis of European civilization through a concrete historical ontology based on human finitude (48) which would reveal the ontic-ontological status of the human practice of making (49). This project stands on two legs because for Hegel as for Heidegger, being appears in producing itself (50). Marcuse was the lone thinker of the 1920s who thought, for a short while, that these two legs could walk together. Later attempts at a Heideggerian Marxism would need to sustain a similar position, though none of them, curiously, took their bearings from Marcuses early work. Despite his obvious sympathy for this position, Feenberg does not rush to an easy synthesis. He clearly pinpoints the main difference. Let me quote this key passage in full. In Heidegger, the contingency of the relation of Dasein to world is never overcome. At most Daseins resoluteness enables it to be itself in the face of its thrownness. Just as Dasein in Heidegger falls into a world, so in Hegel Spirit falls into otherness, but unlike in Heidegger it overcomes this through labor, and thus returns to itself. This whole process, which constitutes the Being of spirit, does not happen to spirit or take place with it; rather it is grasped and comprehended by spirit and is carried out and sustained via this cognition. The process of revealing in Hegel is concrete, as labor and self-recognition in the object of labor. It is also social insofar as spirit is the life of a people and not just of an individual. History then is alienation and return from alienation to a mediated unity with the other (52). The embedded quote here is from Marcuses Hegels Ontology and the Theory of Historicity.5 It shows that Marcuses turn to Hegelfirst perhaps as a supplementation but then, at least in his own view, as a substitutionwas because he rejected an existentialist contingency of worldly experience in favour of the Hegelian necessity of the alienation story grounded in a Marxist ontology of labour. Feenberg shows in detail how the basic concepts of Marcuses thought at this point represent a unique reckoning with the critical and ontological task of 20th century philosophy based on Heideggers and Hegels different readings of Aristotle. I can only note three related points of importance in this context: 1] Marcuse was skeptical of Hegels absolute and read him as an atheist (58); 2] Essence is dialectically constructed as the unrealized potentiality of historical existence (59); 3] Marcuse insisted, against Hegel, that cognition be understood as life and not the reverse (64). Thus, the absolute is understood as a way of life that is the unity in difference of subject and object (67). It is this Hegelian synthesis, understood as a dialectic of self and otherness, a falling into alienation and return to self, that Marcuse judged capable of overcome the historical contingency and necessary inauthenticity of Heideggers Dasein.6 It is the notion that the productivist and practical ontology necessary to addressing the 20th century crisis can be successfully completed only if production is understood as self-production, labour as self-making, and externality encompassed within an expanded self, such that a dialectical reversal of capitalist objectification can be expected. At this point in his text Feenberg inserts a chapter focussed on Lukács to show that Marcuses search for a concrete dialectic based on an ontology of production responded to the current crisis in Marxism. Unlike Hegel and Heidegger, who began with a productivist ontology and yet abandoned it, Marcuses interpretation of the absolute as life aimed to solve the split between subject and object in contemporary Marxism through a form of self-consciousness which is both the revelation of a world and the transformation of that world (80, emphases removed). Feenbergs thesis in the next two chapters is that Marcuses later work continues to search for such a revolutionary consciousness without a satisfactory solution. In his aesthetic theory, for which he is probably best known, the imagination is obviously derived from the model of art but it paints not just the canvas but all of nature (97). For Feenberg, the most promising element of Marcuses late work is that on technology. He argues that Marcuses notion of an aesthetic criterion for the new technical logos [should] be interpreted as an attempt to articulate a substantive, future oriented conception of democracy (109). At this point he links his own philosophy of technology to a critical interpretation of Marcuses relation to Heidegger and a continuation of the project of a Heideggerian Marxism. Feenberg criticizes Marcuse for conflating the scientific concept of nature with the lived experience of nature and claims that, consequently, Marcuse wrongly tied a change in the direction of technology to the idea of a new scientific conception of nature, an idea whose criticism by Habermas has often served to dismiss the whole of Marcuses work.7 This also is worth quoting in full. Why did Marcuse follow this path? That, I think, is a consequence of the way in which he mixed a Heideggerian critique of technology with the early Marxs notion of the alienation of nature. Scientific nature becomes the object of transformative practice when reinterpreted in these terms. The result is no more plausible today than were Marxs similar conclusions in 1844. Marcuse would have avoided this outcome had he pursued the phenomenological approach at which he hints to its logical conclusion. Then he would have been able to ground his critique of technology on the lived experience of nature independent of science (116). As carefully as the way was prepared for this conclusion, it hit me like the last page of an Agatha Christie novel. Unlike all other Marcuse commentators (as far as I know) Feenberg argues not only for the persistence of phenomenological themes in Marcuses later work, but that the failure to acknowledge this influence made it impossible to fulfil his chosen task. Feenberg suggests that the theme of the liberation of the senses would be better grounded in a phenomenology of the sensual character of the lived body than in Marxs 1844 Manuscripts (125), that technology could be better understood as the material correlate of human action (126), that the dead-end of the call for a new science would not be necessary (126), and, most important, that his notion of an aesthetic synthesis of experience could be productively developed (128). This outlines an unrecognized Marcusian contribution to phenomenology in which social critical standards would become available as structures of perception and action (131). The secret is this: though the story is told forward and structured by intellectual history, the philosophical argument pushes the Marcusian project backward to reveal a missed opportunity. Feenbergs conclusion aims to do nothing less than reverse Marcuses path from phenomenology to Marxism while at the same time radicalizing phenomenology toward a critical aesthetic of everyday life. But was this missed opportunity a real possibility? Could Marcuse have developed an explicit phenomenological Marxism to explain his theory of potentialities? His early Hegel interpretation could have provided a starting point. Recall that in Hegels Ontology, the structures of perception would be relative to the practical relations established in the labor process. A phenomenology of the aesthetic Lebenswelt could have been developed to explain the anticipated transcendence of affirmative culture (132). Feenbergs answer is clear. Marcuse missed an opportunity that was a real possibility. In Hegel Marcuse found a way of squaring the circle of modernity. Dialectics now establishes the ontological priority of what Heidegger analyzed as everydayness but it does so in the more complex form of the living and working community, alienating itself and returning to itself in the course of history (136). Despite the fact that both Marcuse and Heidegger saw Marcuses turn to Hegel as a withdrawal from phenomenology, Feenberg tends to read such judgments in purely situational or personal terms (xiv). He must do so to maintain the current possibility of a Heideggerian Marxism that interprets the analysis of Dasein as accomplished through a historical dialectic of labour. II But can a phenomenology of the bodys aesthetic relation to the world ground a dialectical relation of subject and object? If it cannot, then the reversal of alienation that is purportedly prefigured in capitalist objectification is undermined. One would return again to the unmediated duality of capitalist objectification and (absent or merely voluntarist) revolutionary will, an alienation without reversal that could not coonsistently be called alienation any longerfor what is alienation without return? The tripartitegoing-out-from-self, expansion of possibilities in externality, return from alienation to self at a higher levelstory, and all the language and conceptual structure that goes with it, has to be abandoned if the return cannot be phenomenologically grounded. We may ask: is it the task of phenomenology to ground the key component of Marxism that Marxism itself could not ground? Or is the move toward phenomenology from within Marxism to require a profound revision within Marxism itself? Not just of orthodox Marxism and its abandonment of subjective revolutionary will as Paci and Piccone claimed,8 but of the key mediation between objectification and subjective will and desire that grounds the conceptual apparatus of alienation itself. If so, what would we be left with? Heideggerian Marxists have tended to hide this issue behind a Heidegger-inspired exegesis of Marxs texts. Kostas Axelos, in his account of the development of tools and machines into technicist civilization, asserts that it has made life and labour unbearable. The key twist is that capitalist technicism poisons and alienates everything, and only the negativity that is implicated in its very essence will be able to furnish the antidote that can reconcile men with a social and human civilization and technique.9 But a poison need not be an alienation if an alienation demands a reversal. A poison could simply kill. That there is a negativity in the essence of capitalist technicism is exactly what needs to be shown. What could manifest this adequately enough for a theory and convincingly enough for a political practice? When Michel Henry, also mired in exegesis, claims that the reversal of the teleology of life in economic teleology is, in its turn, reversed, he sets that claim on what seems to me an excellent understanding of Marxs critique of political economy; the lack of autarchy of economic reality, the fact that, unintelligible by itself, it is always founded upon a reality of another order by which it is determined and to which it refers.10 But this is not an account of alienation and return (though perhaps the difference is obscured by his language). It is an account of the parasitical nature of economic representations and, perhaps we may say after Heidegger, of all systems of representations, on a more fundamental creative stratum of life. Henrys vision of socialism is of the acual becoming of social substance, the fact that it henceforth merges with the life of men instead of being lost somewhere beyond it in the irreality of abstractionas if the tie that unites individuals could be separated from each one of them [ie. in exchange].11 The recovery of subjective praxis from its loss in objectified representations is thus a grasping of the fundament of human creative activity itself such that the demand for transparency [of social relations under socialism] is nothing other than the phenomenological milieu immanent to individual life the rejection of all transcendence, the refusal to allow the social relation to be constituted beyond this life the assertion of the positive character of life.12 In my view this is a brilliant interpretation, one made possible only by the thorough investigation of the phenomenology of manifestation undertaken earlier,13 but it is no longer an account of alienation and return in which that which is made into object is re-appropriated by the subject at a higher level. It is a story of the parasitism of representations, of ideology as the attempt to conceal the creative fundament of representation as a factor (eg. labour-power as labour) within systems of representations, of the return toward the creative fundament itself. This phenomenological return is not a Hegelian one that can capture its point of departure. It is ever-present under representations and can be recovered by a phenomenological dismantling (Abbau).14 Can there, then, be a régime of the fundament, an organization (like socialism, perhaps) that can be separated from representation? To maintain so is to confuse the phenomenological turn with the Hegelian-Marxist one. Henry does not confuse them, but then his communism takes the form of a machine society producing a superabundance of goods without human intervention,15 a liberation from labour not of labour. One must conclude that, because any régime requires a system of representation, and because systems of representation are parasitic on the creative fundament that produces them, there can be no régime of the creative fundament itself. This understanding grounds a conception of a limited ideological régime in which the ever-presence of the creative fundament is systematically obscured. While this can indeed be made to correspond to one ideal of socialism as an automated leisure society, the point in this context is that it precisely does not, and cannot, return, through a reversal, the objectification of labour to its living praxis. The point of my excursus into Axelos and Henry is to show that Heideggerian Marxism is least successful when it understands itself as a re-instatement of the Hegelian dialectical unity of subject and object that could ground a revolutionary will within capitalist objectification. The separation between these is a historical fact that needs to be understood rather than re-instated by a theory, as if such re-instatement could be anything more than self-delusion. Rather, it is most successful when the critique revises Marxism phenomenologically and generalizes it into a critique of systems of representation. But the price of this revision is the recognition that there can be no system of the creative fundamentwhich Marx adumbrated as labouritself, that parasitic systems will and must persist. It would require a long, but important, disgression to suggest that the political form of socialism to which such a critique corresponds has already shown signs of emergence in the new social movements of our time.16 III Since Feenbergs argument works chronologically as well as historically, his first chapter seeks to establish that Heideggers reading of the Greeks allows him not only to surpass Greek metaphysics but also to show that Greek metaphysics was defined and held back by its understanding of techneæ. It is this argument that is the basis for the claim that a contemporary philosophy of technology is not only a regional inquiry required by the new social and ecological effects of technology (a common claim) but a deeply-rooted taking-over of the task of philosophy per se (a much more radical claim).17 It is this latter claim that is the basis for the contemporary relationship of Heidegger and Marxism. The philosophical question that Feenberg addresses through the relationship of Marcuse to Heidegger is the possibility that a Heideggerian Marxismwhat Michel Henry has called a conception of Being as productioncan assume the mantel not only of a critique of technological civilization but the definition of the task of philosophy itself.18 Heidegger claims that the model of techneæ underlies the two fundamental Greek metaphysical distinctions physis-poieæsis and existence-essence. The first distinction separates that which comes into being by itself from that which comes into being through human activity. Technai are the forms of practical knowledge in human making. Thus, one may suppose that it is the experience of knowledge in human activity that grounds the distinction between such forms and those which operate without a prior idea in the mind of the human actor. Marx utilized this Greek conception, which he took from Aristotle, when he pointed out that what distinguishes the worst architect from the best of bees is this, that the architect raises his structure in imagination before he erects it in reality.19 This prior idea that grounds the construction of useful things is the essence that activity brings into existence. It is thus not too difficult to see that techneæ underlies the existence-essence distinction in the case of objects of poieæsis. The more important, and distinctively Heideggerian, claim is that techneæ also underlies the existence-essence distinction in the case of objects of physis, or nature (as one would say in Latin). Plato applied the existence-essence distinction to physis as well as poieæsis by claiming that the static world of ideas is distinct from and gives the measure to the kinetic world of experience. The Platonic theory of ideas, what Heidegger later called metaphysics, should be understood as the establishment of the model of techneæ for subsequent Greek philosophy and, indeed, philosophy outright insofar as it depends on these two fundamental distinctions. If it is techneæ that holds together the distinctions that ground an understanding of kinesis, movement, then it reigns through all subsequent theory of being and time. Feenberg summarizes: What conclusion do we draw from these historical considerations on anceint Greek philosophy? I will be provocative and say that the philosophy of technology begins with the Greeks and is in fact the foundation of all Western philosophy. After all, the Greeks interpret being as such through the concept of technical making. This is ironic. Technology has a low status in high culture but it was actually there at the origin of that culture and, if we believe the Greeks, contains the key to the understanding of being as a whole (8). This is not the only irony. Feenbergs wording obscures a key point here. It was not the Greek understanding itself that techneæ was the model for philosophy. This is the Heideggerian interpretation of the Greek understanding. Greek philosophy itself, as Feenberg himself documents, denied a distinction between that which is true of that which produces itself and that which is true of that which is produced by humans (8). It is this denial which allows Socrates to argue against Callicles (and, in general, the instrumentalism of the rhetoricians) that human action has an essence just like non-human things. Techneæ became the model for Greek philosophy precisely insofar as it was not understood to be drawn from human action but, instead, as applicable to being as such. Greek philosophy battled the conventionalism of the rhetoricians (nomos) with distinctions that were themselves universalized from the model of human action (logos). In taking over this Heideggerian understanding of the nature of Greek philosophy since the theory of ideas, Feenberg must commit himself to the coincident Heideggerian notion that such philosophy involves a forgetting of the prior origins of philosophyhis version of the Marxian and Nietzschean claim that philosophy does not know itself. Feenberg does not appear to be aware of this, however, as indicated by his puzzlement as to why Heidegger would refer to physis as a form of poieæsis even though it isnt in his Greek grammar (141, footnote 5). To this extent, the notion of being as production cannot be regarded as an original formation of philosophy. One should also underline that the Heideggerian reading of Greek philosophy is by no means self-evident. The work of Hannah Arendt, for example, took off from precisely the same point but argued that the collapse of techneæ and phroneæsis, art and politics, in Heideggers interpretation of Aristotle channels what according to Aristotle pertains to the ethical realm and is connected with the plurality of human affairs into a debate strictly dealing with ontology. The root of this misinterpretation was the pollution of sophia by poieæsis and techneæ explains that the Greek ontologist grants more attention to the being of nature than to his own being. The reason is that Being in the sense of the subsisting presence of nature is that which the activity of production never ceases presupposing and taking for granted.20 This Arendtian critique of Heidegger underlies all attempts (Gadamer, Habermas, etc.) to separate a realm of praxis from techneæ and assert the political steering of contemporary technology. It is not only consistent but reinforcing to say both that Heidegger collapsed Aristotles praxis into techneæ and that techneæ was the model for revealing. But if one wishes, as did Arendt, to rescue an Aristotelian concept of politics as praxis to counterpose to techneæ, then it must be shown, against Heideggers challenge, how the concept of praxis is not indebted to techneæ in its fundamental conception. Feenbergs account of Marcuses path seems the stronger option here. It is, at any rate, the more Heideggerian.21 The understanding of post-Platonic Greek philosophy as governed by the model of techneæ allows a clarification of the specific character of modern philosophy. Whereas the Greeks did not question the origin of essences, modern historicism has revealed the ungrounded character of the eidos. Thus, moderns tend to read Callicles with more sympathy than Socrates (11, 41) and, one might say more generally, modernity is a universalization of the instrumentalism of Greek rhetoric in a new partnership with techneæ. The modern technological revealing sweeps away all concepts of essence and leaves only a collection of fungible stuff available for human ordering in arbitrary patterns (39) because we have discovered the active involvement of human beings in the meaning of beings even if we express this insight in a distorted form as subjectivism and nihilism (39). Here is the claim to distortion againa concept to which any appropriation of the Marxist legacy must give some meaning. Perhaps it is the very fact that, while modern historicism has discovered the activity of humans in the question of essence, the fact of this involvement has been there since Greek philosophy. Most modern thinkers have confused these two elements, whereas Heideggers analysis of Greek philosophy as techneæ allows them to be distinguished. It is likely this confusion which leads to the subjectivism and nihilism which Feenberg rightly diagnoses. There is another characteristic of modern technology that Feenberg passes over in silence, but which is essential for connecting Marxs critique of political economy to the Heideggerian critique of representation, its systematicity. It is precisely the overcoming of essence by fungible stuff, techneæ by Gestell, that knits the various productive activities into a whole. This whole is not the aggregate of a number of similar activities considered together, but an integral whole of activities that mutually refer to each other and function relation to each other: a system. The idea of a system is an essentially modern idea.22 In Henrys words, if we consider the unconcealment proper to modern technology as it is described by Heidegger, we notice that it is one and accomplishes itself globally: within this unconcealment, the fate of the activity of the one who works is identical to that of the raw materials, of form and of its end. The essence of technology is like a structure: the elements co-constituting it receive their intelligibility and their definition from that structure.23 As Heidegger said, modern technology also contains the other possibility that [man] might experience as his essence his needed belonging to revealing (quoted, 40). This would be the Heideggerian version of the reversal that Hegelians call negativity and which grounds their application of the form of the alienation story to history. But note that while a belonging to revealing is, in a certain sense, the corresponding negativity of the forgetting of Being in technological civilization, it does not promise a reversal whereby the structures of technological civilization become de-alienated or authentic (Eigentlich). What possibility does it open? This is a crucial, but less-explored issue. One reason that it is less-explored is that Heideggerian Marxists have been too quick to confuse this Heideggerian negativity of open-ness with a Hegelian one and to opt for the supposed dialectical solution. As I have documented above, Feenberg is by contrast clear about the difference between the Heideggerian and Hegelian forms of appearing in production. A contemporary philosophy of technology thus contains the related possibilities of a critique of technological civilization and a renewal of philosophy, but one which is more of an open field than the expectation of determinate negation. There may be a Heideggerian Marxism, but only if it rids itself of the inherited Hegelianism of dialectical Marxism and confronts the phenomenon of appearing anew. IV How stands it, then, with Feenbergs central claim that a re-evaluation of the Heideggerian-phenomenological element of Marcuses thinking can ground a contemporary philosophy of technology? Feenbergs argument that Marcuse turned to Hegel to ground a notion of revolutionary reversal that couldnt be grounded from a Heideggerian position is compelling. His tracing of lingering phenomenological themes and conceptualizations in Marcuse is conceptually deft and interpretively convincing. But the argument, precisely in bringing back the phenomenological component, tends to leave unresolved, not really even addressed, the underlying issue of the relation between the Hegelian theory of alienation and the phenomenological kinaesthetic of the lived body.24 We have the two legs, but cant be sure if the creature can walk. From this point of view, the intellectual history that Feenberg carefully traces might fall victim to the philosophical problem that drives it forward. Although Marcuse might well have underestimated the phenomenological traces in his later work, he might have been right on the basic point that his adherence to a Hegelian version of negation requires departure from Heidegger and phenomenology. To stand the question on the other leg: Does the philosophy of technology that can be grounded by bringing back phenomenological kinaesthesis allow one to spot an incipient revolutionary will and ground an expectation of reversal? Catastrophe and redemption reads the sub-title to the text. Should it be catastrophe or redemption? Poison without antidote? There are two possible philosophical options here and a divide in the political road: either one wants to heal Marxism by rediscovering Hegelian negation within the Heideggerian critique of metaphysics (redemption) or one recognizes that phenomenological kinaesthesis grounds neither Hegelian negation nor revolutionary will. Despite the brilliance of Feenbergs intellectual history and philosophical analysis, I think that he muddies this alternative. The basis for the two legs, he rightly points out, is that for Hegel as for Heidegger, being appears in producing itself (50). But, for Hegel, the negativity in appearing is manifested as an opposition that grounds a synthesis, whereas, for Heidegger, negativity is a withdrawal, a concealment within unconcealment, that haunts all manifestation as such. Negativity never becomes a second positive and cant be enfolded within a continuous dialectical movement. The political divide is between those who seek to find a revolutionary unity to the plurality of critical social movements of our time and those for whom this plurality in an unsurpassable historical event.25 The most honest form of the first alternative is Marcuses post-Heideggerian path. Feenberg shows that until the late 1960s it takes the form of a Hegelian-Marxist concept of potentiality where potentialities emerge from history and are not bound by the given form of things (20). Its philosophical ground is in a historical and dialectical concept of essence culminating in the concept of the essence of man, which sustains all critical and polemical distinctions between essence and appearance as their guiding principle and model.26 Later, under the influence of the New Left, he argued for a new sensibility in which the values of life would prevail (20). In all its shifts it attempted to link emergent social movements to a revolutionary subjectivity. I would judge this a genuine tragedy, an honest and questing revolutionary sensibility ultimately held back from confronting the novum of its time by a presupposed Hegelian negativity, an episode in the historical tragedy of Marxism itself. Acceptance of the plurality of critical social movements might ground a new politics, not Heideggers but perhaps Heideggerian.27 The philosophical options: To what extent does Feenbergs philosophy of technology expect a Hegelian return from alienation? To what extent does it seek the creative fundament uncovered by the critique of representations? There are two Marcusian threads that Feenberg wants to pull on here: life and democracy. He argues that the value of life in the Marcusian sense is designed into the technical codes by which a society structures itself around a technology. Each such code affirms life within the limits of the technical knowledge and the repressive structure of the dominant regime. Ethical and aesthetic mediations play an essential role in this process, integrating technical principles to a design that coheres with social and natural values (105). In short, he uncovers the Marcusian historical essence of life (Dasein) within the social organization of each technology not (only) within the capitalist social order as a whole. This philosophical analysis grounds both academic studies of, and political interventions in, specific technologies with values inherent in their design and application. If this possibility were sufficiently developed to disturb the background consensus that everywhere trumps tradition (108) based on technology it would unleash a substantive, future oriented conception of democracy (109). Thus, while there are problems with Marcuses approach, at least it offers a properly modern solution to the conundrum of rights and goods while promising a path to the realization of more liberating projects than those of either tradition or business (110). These proposals constitute a valid extension of Marcuses work in the direction of a philosophy of technology, but they are largely silent on the philosophical divide that I have argued must be addressed by any attempt to revive a Heideggerian Marxism. In this context, one might try to make something of Feenbergs insistent and consistent rejection of any return to tradition or pre-modern technologies, which he interprets as nostalgia for a pure immediacy of the phenomenological sort,28 or his acceptance of the simplistic received view of the relation between Husserl and Heidegger as a shift from consciousness to experience which prevents him from bringing the Husserlian critique of modern rationality into relation with Marxism,29 but the hints are too fleeting to be conclusive. For a contemporary philosophy of technology to fulfil the expectation of a critique of technological civilization and a reformation of the task of philosophy itself, it must address two issues that inevitably come with an appropriation of the Heideggerian critique of technology. The first is the notion that the later Greek metaphysics of presence involves a forgetting of the prior origins of philosophy. The second is whether there are limits to a productivist philosophy itselfa question posed equally by contemporary environmental philosophys notion that all beings have an intrinsic worth apart from their instrumental value to humans and by Heideggers later conception of thinking as releasement (Gelassenheit). One wonders whether a Husserlian Marxism might shed some light on these issues through its critique of one-sided rationalism. Feenbergs book doesnt address these questions, in large part because of the failure to ask directly whether the two legs of Marcusian Heideggerian Marxism can effectively walk together. I have suggested that they cant, that either Hegel or Heidegger has to go. To this extent, the philosophical task of the book is obscured by the organizing spine of intellectual history. I think that Feenberg is exactly right about Marcuses latent Heideggerianism, but that Marcuse is right that his move to Hegel had to jettison not only Heidegger but phenomenology outright. Feenbergs philosophy of technology should be watched with great interest as it takes on the huge task of a critique of technological civilization and a reformation of the task of philosophy itself in the manner of Marcuse and Heidegger. This truly stellar book, which has the great merit of bringing the project of phenomenoloigcal Marxism to life again in our own philosophical context, remains as yet unclear whether its hopes are Heideggerian or Hegelian, on which way the revealing will go. 1 (New York and London: Routledge, 2005). References to the book under review are within brackets in the main text. 2 Paul Piccone, Phenomenological Marxism, Telos, No. 9, Fall 1971. 3 Herbert Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man (Boston: Beacon Press, 1964) pp. 153-4. 4 Lucien Goldmann, Lukács and Heidegger: Towards a New Philosophy, trans. William Q. Boelhower (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977). 5 Herbert Marcuse, Hegels Ontology and the Theory of Historicity, trans. S. Benhabib (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987) p. 222. 6 It was actually Karl Löwith, Heideggers first doctoral student, who was the first to criticizein his Habilitationsschrift entitled Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen (1928)the key conflation of social existence with inauthentic existence in Being and Time such that the possibility of an authentic sociality was excluded in principle. See Richard Wolin, Karl Löwith and Martin HeideggerContexts and Controversies: An Introduction in Karl Löwith, Martin Heidegger and European Nihilism, trans. Gary Steiner (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995) pp. 4-6. This perhaps serves to indicate that this criticism is not dependent upon a Marxist affirmation that alienation can be overcome as such. 7 Habermas, like Marcuse, makes no distinction between nature as understood by science and lived nature. Jürgen Habermas, Technology and Science as Ideology, Toward a Rational Society, ans. Jeremy J. Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1970). A recent re-evaluation of this crucial episode in the history of the Frankfurt School by Samir Gandesha rightly notes the two sources of Marcuses position, Marxism and phenomenology, and roots the effectivity of Habermas critique in a marginalization of the world-disclosive conception of language, indicating that a positive appreciation of Marcuses work depends upon an appreciation of the role of phenomenology in disclosing the lived world. Marcuse, Habermas, and the Critique of Technology, John Abromeit and W. Mark Cobb (eds.) Herbert Marcuse: A Critical Reader (New York: Routledge, 2004) pp. 195, 201, 205. 8 Enzo Paci deftly shows the similarity between the part-whole relation analyzed by Husserl in Logical Investigations and the particular-universal status of the proletariat under capitalism, but he doesnt justify the leap to characterizing it as alienation, thereby assuming precisely what is to be shown. The Function of the Sciences and the Meaning of Man, trans. Paul Piccone and James Hanson (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1972) pp. 326-7. Paul Piccone ends his essay, which was written under Pacis influence, with the same ungrounded assumption. Phenomenological Marxism, p. 30. 9 Kostas Axelos, Alienation, Praxis, and Techne in the Thought of Karl Marx, trans. Ronald Bruzina (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1976) pp. 82, 84. 10 Michel Henry, Marx: A Philosophy of Human Reality, trans. Kathleen McLaughlin (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1983) pp. 232, 270. 11 Ibid, p. 298. 12 Ibid. p. 300. Jacques Derrida has pointed out that philosophies of life must weigh carefully whether they understand that the specter weighs, it thinks, it intensifies and condenses itself within the very inside of life, within the most living life, the most singular (or, if one prefers, individual) life with reference to Michel Henry in Specters of Marx, trans. Peggy Kamuf (New York: Routledge, 1994) p. 109. When Karl Marx claimed that labour is the living, form-giving fire
the transitoriness of things, as their formation by living time he seems to have assumed, rather than shown, that the present as living time could throw off the weight of the dead past. Karl Marx, Grundrisse: Introduction to the Critique of Political Economy, trans. Martin Nicolaus (Middlesex:: Penguin, 1973) p. 361. But can life manifest itself, if manifesting is to humans, without death? And if not, human society must make a place for death, as it always has, and the free society can be free from neither death nor the past. 13 That investigation concludes in this way: There exist two specific and fundamental modes in conformity with which the manifestation of what is takes place and is manifested. In the first of these modes, Being manifests itself to the outside, it makes itself unreal in the world
. In the second of these modes, in feeling, Being arises and reveals itself in itelf, integrates itself with self and experiences self
. One may thus read Henrys subsequent book on Marx as an overcoming of the separation of the two modes, which Marxists would call subject and object, by the primacy of the creative fundament. Michel Henry, The Essence of Manifestation, trans. Girard Etzkorn (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973) p. 684. I do not know if Henrys terminology of modes is meant to carry the allusion to Spinoza, but it clearly has the merit of pointing to the phenomenological attempt to overcome the subject-object dualism of modern philosophy. Hegel and Marx attempted to do this also, of course, but through dialectical synthesis rather than phenomenological reduction. 14 I have utilized, in debt to Henry, this understanding of the critique of representation in order to show the parallel between ecology and the critique of political economybetween the two relations labour/labour power and wilderness/naturein Ian Angus, A Border Within: National Identity, Cultural Plurality and Wilderness (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen's Press, 1997) pp. 186-97. 15 Henry, Marx, p. 306. While this is Henrys logic, I do not agree that any ideal of socialism must require an end to creative praxis. Rather, it implies the possibility of appealing outside the system of representation to the creative fundamentwhich would be a political act of Abbau, dismantling, deconstructionwithout expecting that this appeal could itself become systemic. This would require new forms of democracy and political discourse. 16 I hope to have made some contribution to this task in the following texts: A Border Within, pp. 176-85, 191-2; Primal Scenes of Communication: Communication, Consumerism, Social Movements (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2000) Part III; Emergent Publics: An Essay on Social Movements and Democracy (Winnipeg: Arbeiter Ring, 2001). 17 As important a philosopher of technology as Hans Jonas was satisfied with the regional justification. See The Imperative of Responsibility (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984) chapter 1. 18 Michel Henry, The Concept of Being as Production, Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, Vol. 10, No. 2, 1985. 19 Karl Marx, Capital, Vol. 1, trans. Sameul Moore and Edward Aveling (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1970) p. 178. 20 Jacques Taminiaux, The Thracian Maid and the Professional Thinker: Arendt and Heidegger, trans. Michael Gendre (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997) pp. 6, 8. 21 It is interesting to point out that while both Marcuses and Arendts interpretations of Greek philosophy focus on techneæ due to Heideggers influence, Adornos interpretation focusses critically on the identity of thought and being in Greek philosophy. This interpretation obviously parallels that of Marxs critique of Hegel. In contrast to the Heideggerian critique, Adorno sees the account of kinesis in Aristotle as promising because where matter and form touch movement must always and necessarily arise. Even if this touch is not sufficient to bring matter into philosophy and unsettle the identity of thought and being, it does represent the most advanced point of Greek metaphysics for Adorno because it is the source for the concept of mediation. Theodor Adorno, Metaphysics: Concept and Problems, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2001) pp. 99-100, 84. 22 Martin Heidegger, Schellings Treatise on the Nature of Human Freedom, trans. Joan Stambaugh (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1985) pp. 29ff. 23 Michel Henry, The Concept of Being as Production, p. 9. 24 On the phenomenology of the kinaesthetic syntheses operative in corporeality and its relation to Husserls as well as Heideggers phenomenology, see Ludwig Landgrebe, The Phenomenology of Edmund Husserl, ed. Donn Welton (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1981). 25 One might argue that Ive set the bar too high, that the emergence of a revolutionary reversal cant be shown theoretically. For myself, I have once expected enough from Marxism to demand an account of the point from which its own specificity derives. If it doesnt work, if theory and praxis do not become a world-revolutionizing unity, surely its better to go elsewhere. But beyond myself, its not a question of predicting the future, but of showing the revolutionizing moment itself at work in the present. If such a moment is not manifested as such, then Marxism deflates into carping that the age of freedom and equality hasnt arrived. One does not need much theory to see this. 26 Herbert Marcuse, The Concept of Essence, Negations, trans. Jeremy J. Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1968) p. 86. 27 Feenberg doesnt address this question in this book, but in another seems to accept the Marxist critique of new social movements that demands a class politics even while he admits that the labour movement doesnt totalize all social struggles. Transforming Technology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002) p. 62. One of the crucial issues for a politics of anti-hegemonic coalition is what sense of universality it might contain instead of class politics and, in more practical terms, whether an anti-hegemonic alliance might emerge from it. I cannot go into this question here, but I am sure that, if such an alliance should emerge, Marcuses ghost will march with it, whereas Hegels will wait at home with the negativity. 28 Andrew Feenberg, Alternative Modernity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995) p. 223. 29 The phrase is that of Steven Galt Crowell in Husserl, Heidegger and the Space of Meaning (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2001) pp. 131, 182 where he offers a sustained critique of its adequacy. |