[Lecture for the Komaba undergraduates, June, 2003]
What Is Philosophy of Technology?
Andrew Feenberg
Our subject
today is philosophy of technology. I'm going to approach this subject from two
standpoints, first of all historically and then I'll look at the contemporary
options in the field, the various different theories that are currently under discussion.
Before I
begin, I would like to situate the field for you briefly. You may already have
some familiarity with philosophy of science as this is one of the most
prestigious fields of philosophy. It is concerned with the truth of science,
the validity of theories and experimentation. We call these “epistemological”
issues, issues in the theory of knowledge. Science and technology share the
same kind of rational thinking based on empirical observation and knowledge of
natural causality, but technology is not concerned with truth but with
usefulness. Where science seeks to know, technology seeks to control.
Nevertheless, there is more to the story than this simple contrast.
In
traditional societies, the way of thinking of the people is formed by customs
and myths that cannot be explained or justified rationally. Traditional
societies therefore forbid certain kinds of questions which would destabilize their
belief system. Modern societies emerge from the release of the power of
questioning against these traditional forms of thought. The European
Enlightenment of the 18th century demanded that all customs and
institutions justify themselves as useful for humanity. Under the impact of
this demand, science and technology become the new basis for belief. They
reshape the culture gradually to be what we think of as “rational.” Eventually,
technology becomes omnipresent in everyday life and technical modes of thought
predominate over all others. In a mature modern society such as
This culture
is clearly “useful” in all its details in the sense the Enlightenment demanded,
but it is now so all encompassing that larger questions can be asked about its
value and viability as a whole. We can judge it as more or less worthy, more or
less ethically justified, more or less fulfilling. Modernity itself authorizes,
even demands such judgment. This is how it came into being. Now we have moved
beyond usefulness in the narrow sense to the question of the kind of world and
the way of life that emerges in a modern society. Insofar as such a society is
technological at its basis, the issues raised in this larger questioning
concern the field of philosophy of technology. We need to understand ourselves
today in the midst of technology and technical knowledge itself cannot help us.
Philosophy of technology belongs to the self-awareness of a society like ours.
It teaches us to reflect on what we take for granted, specifically, rational
modernity. The importance of this perspective cannot be over-estimated.
Having
introduced you briefly to the field, let me turn now to the historical
perspective on its origins. For this we must go back to ancient
The first of
these is the distinction between what the Greeks called physis and poięsis.
Physis is usually translated as nature. The Greeks understood nature to be that
which creates itself, that which emerges from out of itself. But there are
other things in the world, things which depend on something else to come into
being. Poiesis is the practical activity of making in
which human beings engage when they produce something. We call these created beings artifacts and
include among them the products of art, craft, and social convention.
The word
techne in ancient
The second
fundamental distinction is that between existence and essence. Existence
answers the question whether something is or is not. Essence answers the
question what the thing is. That it
is and what it is appear to be two
independent dimensions of being. In the tradition of Western philosophy,
existence becomes a rather hazy concept. It is not really clear how to define
it. We know the difference between what exists and what does not, for example,
as immediate presence or absence, but there is not much more to say. Most of
the attention is given to essence and its successor concepts as developed by
the sciences because this is the content of knowledge.
These
distinctions are self-evident. They form the basis of all philosophical thought
in the West. I'm sure there are equivalent distinctions in traditional Asian
thought as well. But the relation between these two distinctions is not
obvious, is in fact puzzling. The source of the puzzle is the Greek
understanding of technę, the ancestor of modern technology. Of course the
Greeks did not have technology in our modern sense, but they did have all sorts
of techniques and crafts that were the equivalent for their time of what
technology is for us today. And strange
though it seems, they conceived nature on the model of the artifacts produced
by their own technical activity.
To show this,
I will analyze the relation between the two basic distinctions that I've
introduced, physis and poięsis, and existence and essence. In poięsis, the
distinction between existence and essence is real and obvious. The thing exists
first as an idea and only later comes into existence through human making. But
note that for the Greeks the idea of the artifact is not arbitrary or
subjective but rather belongs to a technę. Each technę contains the essence of
the thing to be made prior to the act of making. The idea, the essence of the
thing is thus a reality independent of the thing itself and of the maker of the
thing. What is more, as we have seen, the purpose of the thing made is included
in its idea. In sum, although humans make artifacts, they do so according to a
plan and for a purpose that is an objective aspect of the world.
On the other
hand, the distinction between existence and essence is not obvious for natural
things. The thing and its essence emerge together and exist together. The
essence does not seem to have a separate existence. The flower emerges along
with what makes it a flower: that it is and what it is “happen,” in a sense,
simultaneously. We can later construct a concept of the essence of the flower,
but this is our doing, not something essential to nature as it is to artifacts. Indeed, the very idea of an essence of the
things of nature is our construction. It lies at the basis of science, episteme
in Greek, the knowledge of things. Unlike the knowledge that is active in
technę, which is essential to the objects the essences of which it defines,
episteme, knowledge of nature, appears to be a purely human doing to which
nature itself would be indifferent. Or is it? Here is where the story gets
interesting.
This
difference between the relation of essence to physis and poiesis
is important for an understanding of Greek philosophy and in fact the whole
philosophical tradition precisely because philosophers have tried so hard to surpass
it. You may recall Plato’s theory of ideas, the foundation of the tradition. For
Plato the concept of the thing exists in an ideal realm prior to the thing
itself and allows us to know the thing. Note how similar this theory is to our
analysis of technę in which the idea is independent of the thing. But Plato does
not reserve this theory for artifacts; rather, it is applied to all being. He relies
on the structure of techne to explain not only artifacts, but nature as well.
Plato understands
nature as divided into existence and essence just as artifacts are and this
becomes the basis for Greek ontology. This has many important consequences. In
this conception there is no radical discontinuity between technical making and
natural self-production because they both share the same structure. Technę,
you'll recall, includes a purpose and a meaning for artifacts. The Greeks
import these aspects of technę into the realm of nature and view all of nature
in teleological terms. The essence of natural things includes a purpose just as
does the essence of artifacts. The world is thus a place full of meaning and
intention. This conception of the world calls for a corresponding understanding
of man. We humans are not the masters of nature but work with its potentials to
bring a meaningful world to fruition. Our knowledge of that world and our action in
it is not arbitrary but is in some sense the completion of what lies hidden in
nature.
What conclusion do we draw from these
historical considerations on ancient Greek philosophy? I will be provocative
and say that the philosophy of technology begins with the Greeks and is in fact
the foundation of all Western philosophy. After all, the Greeks interpret being
as such through the concept of technical making. This is ironic. Technology has
a low status in the high culture of modern societies but it was actually there
at the origin of that culture and, if we believe the Greeks, contains the key
to the understanding of being as a whole.
Now we're going to skip to modern times and
talk about the status of technology in our era. You are probably familiar with
the founders of modern thought, Descartes and Bacon. Descartes promised us that
we would become “the masters and possessors of nature” through the cultivation
of the sciences, and Bacon famously claimed that “Knowledge is power.” Clearly
we are in a different world from the Greeks. We have a very different common
sense from the Greeks so things that seemed obvious to them are not obvious to
us. Of course we share with them the fundamental distinctions between the
things that make themselves, nature, and the things that are made, artifacts,
and between essence and existence. But our
understanding of these distinctions is different from theirs. This is
especially true of the concept of essence. For us essences are conventional
rather than real. The meaning and purpose of things is something we create not
something we discover. The gap between man and world widens accordingly. We are
not at home in the world, we conquer the world. This difference is related to
our basic ontology. The question we address to being is not what it is but how it works. Science answers this question rather than revealing
essences in the old Greek sense of the term.
Note that technology is still the model of
being in this modern conception. This was particularly clear in the 18th
century Enlightenment, when philosophers and scientists challenged the medieval
successors to Greek science with the new mechanistic worldview of Galileo and
In the modern context technology does not
realize objective essences inscribed in the nature of the universe, as does
technę. It now appears as purely instrumental, as value free. It does not respond to inherent purposes, but
is merely a means serving subjective goals we choose as we wish. For modern
common sense, means and ends are independent of each other. Here is a crude example. In
Technology in this scheme of things
encounters nature as raw materials, not as a
world that emerges out of itself, a physis, but rather as stuff awaiting
transformation into whatever we desire.
This world is understood mechanistically not teleologically. It is there
to be controlled and used without any inner purpose. The West has made enormous technical advances
on the basis of this understanding of reality. Nothing restrains us in our
exploitation of the world. Everything is exposed to an analytic intelligence
that decomposes it into usable parts. Our means have become ever more efficient
and powerful. In the 19th century it became commonplace to view
modernity as an unending progress toward the fulfillment of human needs through
technological advance. It was this notion that captured the imagination of the
Japanese in the Meiji era and led to the modernization of Japanese society in
the 20th century.
But for what ends? The goals of
our society can no longer be specified in a knowledge of some sort, a techne or
an episteme, as they were for the Greeks.
They remain purely subjective arbitrary choices and no essences guide us. This has led to a crisis of civilization from
which there seems no escape we know how to get there but we do not know why we
are going or even where. The Greeks
lived in harmony with the world whereas we are alienated from it by our very
freedom to define our purposes as we wish. So long as no great harm could be
attributed to technology, this situation did not lead to serious doubts. Of
course there were always literary protests against modernization. In
I will organize my comments around the
following chart:
Technology is: |
Autonomous |
|
Humanly Controlled |
|
|
|
|
Neutral (complete separation of means and ends) |
Determinism (e.g. modernization theory) |
|
Instrumentalism (liberal faith in progress) |
|
|
|
|
Value-laden (means form a way of life that includes ends) |
Substantivism (means
and ends linked in systems) |
|
Critical Theory (choice of alternative means-ends systems) |
As you can see, technology is defined here along two axes reflecting its
relation to values and human powers. The vertical axis offers two alternatives:
either technology is value neutral, as the Enlightenment assumed, or it is
value-laden as the Greeks believed and, as we will see, as some philosophers of
technology believe today as well. The choice is not obvious. From one
perspective a technical device is simply a concatenation of causal mechanisms.
No amount of scientific study will find in it anything like a purpose. But from
another perspective this misses the point. After all, no scientific study will
find in a 1000 yen note what makes it money. Not everything is a physical or
chemical property of matter. Perhaps technologies, like bank notes, have a
special way of containing value in themselves as social entities.
On the horizontal axis technologies are signified as either autonomous
or humanly controllable. To say that technology is autonomous is not of course
to say that it makes itself. Human beings are still involved, but the question
is, do they actually have the freedom to decide how technology will develop? Is
the next step in the evolution of the technical system up to us? If the answer
is “no” then technology can rightly said to be autonomous in the sense that
invention and development have their own immanent laws which humans merely
follow in acting in the technical domain. On the other hand, technology would
be humanly controllable if we could determine the next step in its evolution in
accordance with our intentions.
Now let me turn to the four boxes defined by the intersection of these
axes.
We have already discussed instrumentalism, the occupant of the box in
which human control and value neutrality intersect. This is the standard modern
view, according to which technology is simply a tool or instrument of the human
species through which we satisfy our needs. As noted in the chart, this view
corresponds to the liberal faith in progress which was such a prominent a
feature of mainstream Western thought until fairly recently.
The next box over to the left is entitled “determinism.” This is the
view so widely held in social science since Marx that the driving force of
history is technological advance. Determinists believe that technology is not
humanly controlled, but that on the contrary it controls humans, that is, it
shapes society to the requirements of efficiency and progress. Technological
determinists usually argue that technology employs advancing knowledge of the
natural world to serve universal features of human nature such as basic needs
and faculties. Each worthwhile discovery addresses some aspect of our nature,
fulfills a basic need or extends our faculties. Food and shelter are such needs
and motivate some advances. Technologies like the automobile extend our feet
while computers extend our brains. Technology is rooted on the one side in
knowledge of nature and on the other in generic features of the human species.
It is not up to us to adapt technology to our whims but on the contrary, we
must adapt to technology as the most significant expression of our humanity.
These two views, instrumentalism and
determinism, have an interesting history in
The box on the lower left of the chart is
titled “substantivism.” This is a more complex and interesting position than
those we have reviewed so far. The term “substantivism” was chosen to describe
a position which attributes substantive values to technology in contrast with
views such as instrumentalism and determinism which view technology as neutral
in itself. The contrast here is actually between two types of value. The
neutrality thesis does attribute a value to technology but it is a merely
formal value, efficiency, which can serve any number of different conceptions of
the good life. A substantive value on the contrary involves a commitment to a
specific conception of the good life. If technology embodies a substantive
value, it is not merely instrumental and cannot be used for the different
purposes of individuals or societies with different ideas of the good. Using
technology for this or that purpose would be a specific value choice in itself,
and not just a more efficient way of realizing a pre-existing value of some
sort.
This distinction can be clarified best with
examples. Take the extreme difference between a religion such as Buddhism or
Christianity and money. Religions are based on substantive value choices,
choices that reflect a preferred way of life and exclude other disapproved
alternatives. Money is a purely formal basis of social action. It can be used
to buy an infinite variety of different things and integrated to different and
contradictory ways of life without prejudice. In principle, it seems as though
money carries no particular substantive value in itself but can serve any value
system. The question posed by substantive theory is whether technology is more
like religion or more like money, as I have just described it.
Substantive theory replies that
technology is more like religion. When you choose to use technology you do not
simply render your existing way of life more efficient, you choose a different
way of life. Technology is thus not simply instrumental to whatever values you
hold. It carries with it certain values that have the same exclusive character
as religious belief. But technology is even more persuasive than religion since
it requires no belief to recognize its existence and to follow its commands. Once
a society goes down the path of technological development it will be inexorably
transformed into a technological society, a specific type of society dedicated
to values such as efficiency and power. Traditional values cannot survive the
challenge of technology.
Actually, this vision of technology can be extended to money as well.
Although it seems as though money is a neutral instrument of our purposes, on
closer examination we realize that it is much more than that. We say there are
things money can’t buy such as love and happiness. Yet people do try to buy
them all the time with disappointing results. Bought love is after all
something quite different from the real thing. Those who base their whole lives
on the power of money have poor lives. Money is fine in its place, but outside
its place it corrupts and diminishes people and things. So in a sense money too
has a substantive value and basing a way of life on it is a positive choice and
not the best one at that.
You will have noticed the similarity between substantive theory of
technology and determinism. In fact most substantive theorists are determinists
as well. But the position I have characterized as determinism is usually
optimistic and progressive. Both Marx and the modernization theorists of the
post-War era believed that technology was the neutral servant of basic human
needs. Substantive theory makes no such assumption about the needs technology
serves and is critical rather than optimistic. In this context the autonomy of
technology is threatening and malevolent. Once unleashed technology becomes
more and more imperialistic, taking over one domain of social life after
another. In the most extreme imagination of substantivism, a Brave New World
such as Huxley describes in his famous novel overtakes humanity and converts
human beings into mere cogs in the machinery. This is not utopia—the “no place”
of an ideal society, but dystopia—a world in which human individuality has been
completely suppressed. Huxley has people produced on assembly lines for
specific social purposes and conditioned to believe exactly those things that
adapt them to their function. People have become, as Marshall McLuhan once said, the “sex organs of the machine world.”
The most famous substantive theorist was Martin Heidegger, a major 20th
century German philosopher. Heidegger argued that modernity is characterized by
the triumph of technology over every other value. He noted that Greek
philosophy had already based its understanding of being on technical making and
argued that this starting point culminates in modern technology. Where the
Greeks took technę as the model of being in theory, we have transformed being
technically in practice. Our metaphysics is not in our heads but consists in
the real technical conquest of the earth. This conquest transforms everything
into raw materials for technical processes, including human beings themselves.
Not only are we constantly obeying the dictates of the many technical
systems in which we are enrolled, we tend to see ourselves more and more as
devices regulated by medical, psychological, athletic, and other functional
disciplines. I do not know if you have so many of these books in Japan as we do
in America, but in our bookstores you can find the equivalent of operating manuals
for every aspect of life: love, sex, raising children, eating, exercise, making
money, having fun, and so on and so forth. We are our own machines.
But, Heidegger argues, although we may control the world through our
technology, we do not control our own obsession with control. Something lies
behind technology, a mystery we cannot unravel from our technological
standpoint. Where we are headed is a mystery too. The West in Heidegger’s view
has reached the end of its rope. In his last interview, he stated, “Only a God
can save us.”
We come now to the last box, the one I have
entitled “critical theory.” This is where I place myself. Critical theory of
technology holds that human beings need not await a God to change their
technological society into a better place to live. Critical theory recognizes
the catastrophic consequences of technological development highlighted by
substantivism but still sees a promise of greater freedom in technology. The
problem is not with technology as such but with our failure so far to devise
appropriate institutions for exercising human control over it. We could tame
technology by submitting it to a more democratic process of design and
development.
Consider the parallel case of the economy. A
century ago it was believed that the economy could not be democratically
controlled, that it was an autonomous power operating according to inflexible
laws. Today we assume the contrary, that we can influence the direction of
economic development through our democratic institutions. Critical theory of
technology argues that the time has come to extend democracy to technology as
well. It thus attempts to save the Enlightenment values that have guided
progress for the last several hundred years without ignoring the threat to
which that progress has led.
As you can see from the chart, critical
theory shares traits of both instrumentalism and substantivism. It agrees with
instrumentalism that technology is in some sense controllable, and it agrees
with substantivism that technology is also value-laden. This seems a
paradoxical position since precisely what cannot be controlled in the substantivist
view are the values embodied in technology. According to substantivism the
values contained in technology are unique to technology as such. They include efficiency and power, goals
which belong to any and every technical system. Insofar as we use technology,
we are engaged with the world in a maximizing and controlling fashion. This
approach to the world determines a technological way of life. Obviously human
control would have little significance if every way of life based on technology
realized the same values. The element of human control would be like the choice
between soaps in the supermarket, trivial and delusory. How then does critical
theory conceive the value-ladenness of technology
such that human control matters?
According to critical theory the values embodied
in technology are socially specific and are not adequately represented by such
abstractions as efficiency or control. Technology frames not just one way of
life but many different possible ways of life, each of which reflects different
choices of design and different extensions of technological mediation. I use
the word “frame” here purposely. All the pictures in the museum have frames but
they are not in the museum for that reason. Frames are boundaries and holders
for what lies within. Similarly, efficiency “frames” every possible technology
but does not determine the values realized within that frame.
Does this mean that technology is neutral,
as instrumentalism believes? Not quite: modern societies must all aim at
efficiency in those domains where they apply technology, but to claim that they
can realize no other significant values besides efficiency is to overlook the
obvious differences between them. What is worse, it overlooks the difference
between their current miserable state and a better condition we can imagine and
for which we can struggle. One must look down on mankind from a very great
height indeed not to notice the difference between efficient weapons and
efficient medicines, efficient propaganda and efficient education, efficient exploitation
and efficient research! This difference is significant socially and ethically
and so cannot be discounted as thinkers like Heidegger would claim.
Nevertheless,
the substantivist critique of instrumentalism does
help us to understand that technologies
are not neutral tools. Means and ends are connected. Thus even if some sort of human
control of technology is possible, it is not instrumental control. In critical theory technologies are not seen
as tools but as frameworks for ways of life. The choices open to us are
situated a higher level than the instrumental level. We cannot agree with the
instrumentalist that “Guns don't kill people, people kill people.” Supplying people with guns creates a social
world quite different from world in which people are disarmed. We can choose which world we wish to live in
through legislation either making the possession of guns legal or illegal. But this is not the sort of choice the
instrumentalist claims we make when we control technology. This is what you
might think of as a meta-choice, a choice at a higher level determining which
values are to be embodied in the technical framework of our lives. Critical
theory of technology opens up the possibility of thinking about such choices
and submitting them to more democratic controls. We do not have to wait for a god to save us
as Heidegger expostulated but can hope to save ourselves through democratic
interventions into technology.
You will no
doubt want to know more about these democratic interventions. Clearly, it would
not make much sense to hold an election between devices or designs for
technologies. The public is not sufficiently concerned, involved, and informed
to choose good politicians at this time, much less good technologies. So, in
what sense can democracy be extended to technology under current conditions?
Admittedly, this is a problematic hope. But not an absurd one. People affected
by technological change sometimes protest or innovate in ways that promise
greater participation and democratic control in the future. Where it used to be
possible to silence all opposition to technical projects by appealing to
progress, today communities mobilize to make their wishes known, for example,
in opposition to nuclear power plants in their neighborhood. In a rather
different way the computer has involved us in technology so intimately that our
activities have begun to shape its development. Consider that email on the
Internet was introduced by skilled users and did not originally figure in the
plans of the designers at all. Yet today email is the most used function of the
Internet and one of the most important contributions of the computer to our
lives. I could show you similar examples from medicine, urban affairs, and so
on. Each one seems a small matter but perhaps all together they are
significant.
Critical
theory of technology detects in examples such as these a trend toward greater
participation in decisions about design and development. The public sphere
appears to be opening slowly to encompass technical issues that were formerly
viewed as the exclusive preserve of experts. Can this trend continue to the
point where citizenship will involve the exercise of human control over the
technical framework of our lives? We must hope so for the alternative appears
to be certain destruction. Of course the problems are not only technological.
Democracy is in bad shape today on all fronts, but no one has come up with a
better alternative. If people are able to conceive and pursue their intrinsic
interest in peace and fulfillment through the political process, they will
inevitably address the question of technology along with many other questions
that hang in suspense today. We can only hope this will happen sooner rather
than later.